On the
Topicality of Selected Aspects of Herbert Marcuse's Works
Christian Fuchs
christian@igw.tuwien.ac.at
(German Version/Deutsche Version: Zur Aktualität ausgewählter Aspekte des Werks Herbert Marcuses)
The
goal of this work is the discussion of selected aspects of the works of Herbert
Marcuse in reference to postfordist, neo-liberal and information-societal capitalism.
Whereas the material conditions we have reached would make an immediate transition
into the realm of freedom possible, the one-dimensional society forestalls qualitative
social change in new ways. One-dimensional society still produces one-dimensional,
false consciousness and false needs. In this situation of global crisis, Marcuse’s
dialectical concepts of technology, democracy and culture and his dialectic
of liberation are decisive. Whereas liberation seems to become subjectively
almost impossible, it would objectively be obvious. Marcuse’s utopian thinking
and his philosophy of practice are essentially important in such a situation.
The search for potentially revolutionary subjects and the strengthening of their
self-organisation are tasks of the dialectical unity of theory and practice.
One of Marcuse’s most important theses is still true: it says that we “vacillate
throughout between two contradictory hypotheses: (1) that advanced industrial
society is capable of containing qualitative change for the foreseeable future;
(2) that forces and tendencies exist which may break this containment and explode
the society. I do not think that a clear answer can be given” (Marcuse 1964:
xlvii).
Contents:
Introduction:
Theory and Practice
1. Technology
and Utopia
2. Revolutionary
Subject
3. Democracy
and Fascism
4. Culture
5. Conclusion
Herbert
Marcuse has correctly identified the relationship of theory and practice as
a dialectical one. Critical practical action has to know to what it is referring,
what it wants to change and towards which goals a sublating movement can lead
to. Theory that does not point out the historical situation and possibilities,
is not useful for an emancipatory practice.
Marcuse
pointed out that a theory that does not come along with practical aspects of
capitalism can not contribute to practical aspects of emancipation (Marcse 1972:
40). A critical theory of society can point out the development of existing
social relationships and how they can be changed. Critical theory can line out
the possibilities of change in a certain historical situation. It also encompasses
stimulations of phantasy because imagination involves a high degree of autonomy
in an unfree world. It can go beyond the existing totality and anticipate future
developments (Marcuse 1937a: 122). Critical theory should line out how the possibilities
of social change and emancipation are transforming. It has an anticipating,
critical quality, it projects and design possible types of practice. Critical
theory points out general aspects in specific ones, it names and characterices
aspects of existing society and tendencies that could be blocked in practical
actions (Marcuse 1975: 143).
Theory
is necessary in order to understand the world we live in – it has to understand
what the world has done to man and what it can do to man (Marcuse 1964: 183).
The language employed by critical theory differs from the one used in daily
life, because the latter is being coined by a dominating, one-dimensional language
that does not describe complex relationships adequately (ibid.: p. 207f). By
uncovering the rationality of irrationality that governs society, critical theory
relates to practical aspects (ibid.: 238).
In
the current phase of capitalism which is characterised by social relationships
that become more and more precarious, but in which the material preconditions
of liberation are more developed than ever and people are becoming more and
more ignorant of the possibilities posed, the connecting of theory and practice
is very important. The Critical Theory of Herbert Marcuse has not lost its topicality
by the grand crisis of society which is also a crisis of the left and of Marxism.
On the contrary, the collapse of the soviet-system has shown that capitalism
is not the better alternative, that state-“socialism” as well as the western
types of capitalism are no sustainable types of society. This is shown clearly
by the widening of the global problems.
The thinking of Marcuse (as well as the one of Marx) is very important in this
situation of crisis in order to transform society in such a way that humane
paths of development can be guaranteed. I want to point out the topicality of
four aspects of Marcuses’ thinking that are personally very relevant to me:
1. Technology and utopia, 2. Revolutionary subject, 3. Democracy and fascism,
4. Culture. There would be further aspect, but I can not consider them here
in detail.
I
personally consider technology as a generally organised unity of means, procedures,
knowledge, abilities and processes that are necessary in order to achieve defined
goals. Technology is part of the antagonisms of capitalism and hence it also
contributes to the existence of these antagonisms. The relationship of means
and ends has been reversed in modern society: Ends are not identified which
shall be achieved by making use of technology, but technology has become an
end in itself. Its main purpose nowadays as a specific means of production is
the effective organisation of capital accumulation. Technology does not serve
humankind in order to make its existence easier by mediating the metabolism
between man and nature, it serves capital in order to exploit labor. It is a
means for producing surplus value. Hence it is affirmative technology. An antagonism
is constituted by the fact that generally speaking technology makes the existence
of man easier, but in capitalism it is a means of domination and exploitation
that contributes to the destruction of mankind and nature. By applying technology,
the rate of surplus value is increased by reducing the relative amount of necessary
labour. Technology deporsonalises domination, it steps in between the relationship
of capitalist and worker. Wage laborers are an appendage to fixed capital. On
the one hand in a technological sense, because the means of production can not
be operated by single individuals; they can only be operated in the framework
of the division of labour (separation of producer and means of production).
Wage laborers are – as poined out by Marx – free in a double sense. This also
refers to the fact that the means of production are not owned by the immediate
producers. On the other hand this appendage also can be seen in a social sense
because the means of labour confront the laborers in the form of capital.
Marcuse
had very similar ideas: Technology in capitalism means a special type of social
control for him. These controls have totalitarian tendencies. Hence no neutrality
of technology can be claimed. The mass media coin and manipulate consciousness.
In capitalism, technology means social control and domination. The technological
apparatuses determine social needs, abilities, job relationships and attitudes
– and hence the types of social control and coherence (Marcuse 1961: 45).
Marcuse
says that the negative aspects of automation dominate: „In the present situation,
the negative features of automation are predominant: speed-up, technological
unemployment, strengthening of the position of management, increasing impotence
and resignation on the part of the workers. The chances of promotion decline
as management prefers engineers and college graduates” (Marcuse 1964: 29f).
The technologies of production change consciousness in specific ways. The fixing
of labor forces to automated and semi-automated reactions is a „exhausting,
stupefying, inhuman slavery” (Marcuse 1964: 25). The capitalist employment of
technology can be summarised by the formula: technological progress = more wealth
of society = more slavery (Marcuse 1972: 13). Marcuse says that the existing
means and possibilities of control have been joined by a new momentum that is
connected with the standards of technological progress, with computerisation,
the technological perfection of gathering data and with surveillance (Marcuse
1972: 13).
He
describes a tendency of workers being really interested in the corporations
they work in. 30 years later this “participation of the workforce” is termed
participative management and has become one of the most important elements of
the theory of management. In fact, it does not mean a humanisation of work,
rather new ideological mechanisms that shall guarantee capital accumulation
and end the crisis of capital by integrating the workforce psychologically.
Marcuse
says that by automation the amount of living labor power that is necessary decreases,
living labor transforms itself into dead labour. Hence there is a tendency of
the law of value coming to an end. This also applies for the concepts of surplus
value and the organic composition of capital. This means that by the decrease
of industrial labor the classical concepts of the labor theory of value are
less applicable. On the one hand we are witnessing the sublation of labor, on
the other hand labor is the source of profit. Marcuse argues that this antagonism
causes technological unemployment and poverty.
Max
Horkheimer (1946) spoke about instrumental reason, Herbert Marcuse referred
to the same phenomena as technological rationality. This describes the fact
that in the advanced industrial society something that is not obvious, seems
to be self-evident. Certain reactions are automatised, they are no longer questioned.
Marcuse argues that the important aspects of these actions are that they are
not only instrumental, they also seem to be very reasonable (Marcuse 1941: 293).
These effects which also relate to the antagonisms of technological applications
have been described by Marcuse in his One-Dimensional Man and many other of
his writing. He pointed out in his analyses of German fascism, that technological
rationality is also characteristic of fascism. He says that the German pragmatic
sees everything – also the totalitarian regime – from the aspect of his own material advantages.
He has adapted his thinking, feelings and actions to the technological rationality
of National-Socialism (Marcuse 1942: 25).
In
German fascism, Marcuse argues, people are appendages to the instruments of
production, destruction and communication, although they act with a high degree
of personal initiative, spontanity and personality. Their actions are adapted
to the operation of this machine. The moral of combat has become a part of technology,
the Nazi-system also applies mental technologies (see Marcuse 1942: 47f). In
National-Socialism all values, patterns of thinking and acting are determined
by the necessity of the functioning of the machinery of production, destruction
and domination (ibid.: 48).
Society
and technology are interrelated. Depending on how this relationship is being
described, different positions can be identified: If the emhasis is on technology
determining society, we can speak of a technological determinism. Such positions
often hold that the effects caused by the application of technology result from
technology as it is. If the main emphesis is on the genesis of technology (=the
process of developing new technologies) in such a way that society determines
the application and the resulting consequences of
technology,we can speak of social constructivism (see e.g. Bruno Latour
1987). Such positions argue that the genesis of technology is a social process
and that technology is a social construction. They further hold that the social
consequences of technological applications are bulit into the technologies during
the process of construction. Hence such positions argue that a certain technology
must result in specific consequences. Maybe, such approaches overlook
that the application of technology can gather momentum and that certain aspects
can not be forseen. And one also surely can not generally conclude that all
technologies must have certain consequences that are well-known in advance.
Besides
technological determinism and social constructivism there is also a dialectical
position: Society and technology are related dialectically, there are interrelationships
and mutual dependencies. On a microscopic level (concerning the elements of
a system), technology can be seen as a sub system of society. Society influences
technology in such a way that it can design technologies and decide how they
should be applied. There is also a downward causation, technology influences
society, and so social consequences of the application of technology emerge.
On the one level, we have the emergence of social consequences, on the other
the emergence of new technologies and new qualities of existing technologies.
The consequencs can not be fully foreseen, quite often there are unwanted effects.
Both chance and necessity show their effects. The application of technology
can cause social problems as emergent phenomena of society.
Such
a dialectical methodology enables us to take into account the interrelationships
of technology and society in a non-reductionist manner. The genesis of technology
as well as the consequences of technology are considered. Technological determinism
is a reductionistic methodology, it reduces social problems to technological
aspects of society. Social constructivism argues projectively, it projects social
processes and actions onto technology by claiming that the consequences of technology
can already be found in technology itself. Dialectical methodologies on the
contrary hold that antagonisms are important. They do not say: either this or
that, but: both at the same time. I.e.: Technology influences society and society
influences technology. Another distinction that should be made is the one between
technological pessimism and technological optimisms: The former interprets the
influence of society on technology (and vice versa) very positively, the latter
mainly stresses negative consequences of technology. Again a dialectical position
is the best one, one that judges technology by analysing its embededness into
society.
According
to Herbert Marcuse, technology is not – as argued e.g. by Max Weber and Arnold
Gehlen – value-free. In capitalist society, which has taken on totalitarian
aspects – technology can not be separated from its use. Marcuse considers technological
society to be a system of domination that “operates already in the concept and
construction of techniques” (Marcuse 1964: S. xlviii). At some points in Marcuses’
works one could get the imagination that he sees technology itself as domination,
not domination as a social relationship which makes use of technology. E.g.
he says that not only the usage of technology is domination, but also that technology
is domination over nature and humans (Marcuse 1965b: 179).
Such
shortcomings are only an exception from the rule in his works. Generally Marcuse
argues that technology is a dialectial category, hence that it depends on its
embededness into society and the social framework of its usage. But due to such
passages as just mentioned, Marcuse was sometimes put in line with technological
determinists such as Spengler, Schelsky, Gehlen, Freyer, Ellul, Heidegger, Jünger,
Habermas or Mumford. But in fact, Marcuse criticised the bourgeoise technological
pessimists many times. He e.g. said that all programs with anti-technological
character serve those who see human needs as a side-product of the valorisation
of technology. The enemies of technology would work into the hands of
the terrorist technocracy. Philosophies of a simple life would be needed to
make people suspicious about liberation and its possible instruments (Marcuse
1941: 315f).
When
Marcuse says, that domination is a technology (Marcuse 1964: 158), he does not
mean it in a technological-determinist manner, but he wants to express that
besides the execution of domination with the help of technology it can be said
that the execution of power also can be seen as an aspect of technology as a
broad concept in the sense of a social-technology (Sozialtechnologie). At another
instance Marcuse says: “Technology as such cannot be isolated from the use to
which it is put” (Marcuse 1964: xlviii). This also outlines his refusal of technological
determinism.
For
Marcuse, technology as such does neither mean domination, nor liberation, nor
neutrality. He sees liberation as a social process which needs a certain level
of development of the produvtive forces, but which can only be established socially
and during the course of social struggles. He says that the liberating aspects
of technology are not part of technological progress as such, they presuppose
social changes which also refer to the fundamental economic institutions and
relationships (Marcuse 1957: 238).
Marcuse’s
concept of technology is a dialectical one: On the one side he supposes that
technology is used in capitalism in such a way that people are forced into line
and become powerless. A libertarian use of technology does not seem possible
for him under such circumstances. But if post-capitalist relationships could
be established, Marcuse argues, certain technologies could be used in order
to reduce social necessary labor to a minimum und to give a maximum of freedom
and self-determination to the individuals. In such a case technology would not
mean gleichschaltung, manipulation and the end of individuality, but the possibility
of wealth for all and of an “existence in free time on the basis of fulfilled
vital needs” (Marcuse 1964: 231).
Marcuse
again and again points out that certain developments are a necessary foundation
for the historical level of mankind where it is possible to make use of technology
in order to establish a world of freedom – one without exploitation, misery
and fear (Marcuse 1965a: 123), a technological and natural environment that
is not dominated by violence, ugliness, limitedness and brutality (Marcuse 1972:
12). But it is also possible, Marcuse argues, that technological developments
lead to standardisation of thinking and acting, technological rationality, one-dimensional
and false consciousness and false needs. He stresses this ambivalence which
concerns modern technologies and that fundamental social change does not necessarily
take place. He e.g. says that he wants to stress that he does not (yet) judge
technological developments, they could either be progressive and humanising
or regressive and destructing (1966b: 172). Another time he writes that technology
can put forward authoritaritiveness as well as freedom, lack as well as affluence,
hard labor as well as its abolishment (Marcuse 1941: 286). Not technology and
the machine are leverages of suppression for Marcuse, but the existence of masters
who determine the amount, life time, power and importance of machines as well
as the role they play in life.
Today,
if we take a look at sociology of technology, we on the one hand find very optimistic
views concerning technology which argue that the new technologies will lead
to global wealth and freedom. On the other hand there are very pessimistic argumentations,
as for example in radical- or eco-feminism, which see modern technology as inherently
patriarchal, in-humane, rascist and even fascist. Hence it is argued that we
should return to a simpler type of society that relies on subsistence production.
This clearly would result in a society that is dominated by hard work. Marcuse
would not have qualified such a society as a free one, even if there are no
capitalists in it, because freedom also means the abolishment of hard work and
a maximum of free time. Both argumentations seem to be a little bit short-sighted,
they do not conceive the relationship of society and technology dialectically.
On
the contrary, we find sociologies of technologies as the ones of Marcuse or
Marx which are neither very optimistic, nor very pessimistic, but which assume
that social problems are somehow connected with technological progress, but
that this is not caused by technology as such. The causes are the capitalist
usage of technology and the antagonisms of capitalism. Marx pointed out that
it is not the machinery as such that causes social problems such as unemployment.
He said that machinery would be “be the most powerful
means for increasing the productiveness of labour — i.e., for shortening the
working-time”[1] (Marx 1867:
425). Marx sees this as a very positive aspect of technology, and hence he argues
that an end should and can be put to wage labour: “In fact, the realm of freedom actually begins only where
labour which is determined by necessity and mundane considerations ceases; thus
in the very nature of things it lies beyond the sphere of actual material production”
(Marx 1894: 828)
Marx
sees technological determinism as a means of bourgeois thinkers in order to
persuade the workers that their opponent is not capital as a social relationship,
but technology as such.
“The
contradictions and antagonisms inseparable from the capitalist employment of
machinery, do not exist, they say, since they do not arise out of machinery,
as such, but out of its capitalist employment! Since therefore machinery, considered
alone, shortens the hours of labour, but, when in the service of capital, lengthens
them; since in itself it lightens labour, but when employed by capital, heightens
the intensity of labour; since in itself it is a victory of man over the forces
of Nature, but in the hands of capital, makes man the slave of those forces;
since in itself it increases the wealth of the producers, but in the hands of
capital, makes them paupers-for all these reasons and others besides, says the
bourgeois economist without more ado, it is clear as noon-day that all these
contradictions are a mere semblance of the reality, and that, as a matter of
fact, they have neither an actual nor a theoretical existence. Thus he saves
himself from all further puzzling of the brain, and what is more, implicitly
declares his opponent to be stupid enough to contend against, not the capitalistic
employment of machinery, but machinery itself“
(Marx 1867: 465).
Marx’
concept of technology is a dialectical one: He generally sees technology as
a means that simplifies the existence of man, that gives him more time and space
for the free development of individuality and for self-determination. In a free-society
automation and technological progress would create well-rounded individuals
that live in a society “where nobody has one exclusive
sphere of activity but each can become accomplished in any branch he wishes,
society regulates the general production and thus makes it possible for me to
do one thing today and another tomorrow, to hunt in the morning, fish in the
afternoon, rear cattle in the evening, criticise after dinner, just as I have
a mind, without ever becoming hunter, fisherman, herdsman or critic” (Marx/Engels
1845/46: 33).
But the
capitalist usage of technology would in fact cause contrary effects: lengthening
of the labor day, unemployment and poverty. Marx is neither a technological
optimist, nor pessimist. He argues that machinery can be used in a positive
as well as in a negative sense. But this would depend on the social context,
especially on the economic system. What is relevant and decisive is the embededness
of technology into society. Marx can not image positive aspects of technology
in capitalism. He both stresses the consequences of the capitalist usage of
technology as well as the social framework which is very important for the usage
of technology and its effects on society.
The
topicality of a dialectical concept of technology that stands in the traditions
of Marcuse and Marx can also be seen in the context of the rise of computer-technologies
and modern information and communication technologies (ICT). Hence an assessment
of these technologies should be ambivalent. One the one hand they lead to the
restructuration, de-centralisation and flexibilisation of capitalism, they mediate
de-realisation, simulation and virtualisation of reality, they maximize the
potential of destruction of war technology, they produce antagonisms and contribute
to the widening of the global problems, they promote unemployment, dequalification,
surveillance, they are a medium and result of rationalisation and economic globalisation
and hence they are entangled into the social problems that result from these
phenomena; they mediate the restructuration of corporations in space and time
and are mainly applied in order to maximize profit. Social inequalities are
reflected in cyberspace. But on the other hand, new media also make the virtual
construction of identities possible, they can simplify the access to and the
distribution of information, they make co-operation and communication easier,
they can mediate cultural interchange and a cultural unity in diversity, they
reduce the social necessary labor and they can promote mental activities. Modern
technologies are subject to a dialectic that has already been described by Karl
Marx and Herbert Marcuse. Both argue that it is not all about abolishing technology,
but that a humane and sustainable usage of technology is possible (if the current
social relationships are radically changed). Of course this does not apply e.g.
for military technology, a liberated society would have to get rid of those
technologies that form destructive forces. But this does not apply to all computer
technologies (in contrast to nuclear technology), because it is the military
application of these technology that results in destructive forces. Alternative
usages of computer technologies could make a pacified existence possible that
goes beyond material and psychological shortages. The struggle for existence
could come to an end. All of this would presuppose a new type of society.
Concerning
the usage of modern media in social struggles, the situation is also ambivalent:
On the one hand we have a mass-mediated production and simulation of hyper-reality
that generates new meanings by de-contextualising symbols and pictures and arranging
these symbols as a new whole. This new whole has new meanings which can manipulate
and direct public opinion in certain ways. In this context the thesis of cultural
industry – that has been formulated by Marcuse, Adorno and Horkheimer and which
says that the cultural industry produces false, consciousness, one-dimensional
mass consciousness (Marcuse 1964) and instrumental reason (Horkheimer 1946)
– is true. New technologies are applied functionally in these ways. On the other
hand there is the possibility for protest movements to make use of new media
as means of supporting their self-organisation (see Fuchs 2001). New technologies
reflect social relationships of domination, nonetheless protest movements can
make use of them. Protest in real life can be supported by a virtual culture
of protest and a technologically mediated optimisation of political structures
of self-organisation.
ICT
as the Internet have mediated important transformations of capitalism. Computer
technologies can be seen as medium and result of rationalisation: Capitalism
needs a permanent increase of productivity. Hence an ever increasing rationalisation
is necessary. Computer technology is medium and result of rationalisation and
of the re-structuring of capitalism. Its genesis is a logical result of the
development of the capitalist mode of production. At the same time it is medium
of the substition of human labor power by machines. A logical consequence is
unemployment. The economic diffusion of computer technology is also related
to the crisis of fordism. As a reaction to the relative fall of the profit rates,
computerisation and automation have been put forward in order to save labor
costs and to increase the rates of profit again.
Technological
artefacts reflect social relationships of domination and property. This also
applies to the Internet. The access to cyberspace demands financial resources
for telephone, modem, computer, Internet Service provider etc., but at the same
time we are witnessing an increasing social gap. Only 2-3% of the world population
have access to the Net, these are mainly white, male US-americans. So what we
have is the reflection of social dichotomies concerning class, gender, origin,
age and qualification. There is no “free” access , the call for access for all
is technologically deterministic and does not take into account that this would
have to include a radical transformation of the capitalist world system. Africa
poses about 12% of the world population, but only has about 2% of all telephone
connections. On average there are less than 2 telephone connections per 1000
inhabitants in Africa. The Internet is mainly a means of realising profit, it
has been transformed from a military technology (ARPA-Net) to a means of restructuring
and accelerating business processes, it is a location of capital accumulation
and a means of advertising that encompasses interactive and multimedia dimensions.
Politics is a minority field in the World Wide Web, at maximum 1-2% of all websites
have political contents, the main contents on the Net are sex and commerce.
Nonetheless,
modern ICT can support self-organising political movements. Global networking
and the acceleration of communications can be very helpfull. There are many
examples that show that critical and oppositional forces can worke and organise
themselves more efficiently by making use of ICT. ICT are part of those structures
that conserve domination, but they also pose possibilities for networking and
emancipatory self-organisation (see Fuchs 2001).
Let
us summarise some aspects of modern ICT that are important for social transformations
that we are witnessing today:
Mainly
point one shows that ICT are also medium and result of the economic globalisation
of capitalism. On the one hand they make the generation of temporal and spatial
distance possible, hence local processes are influenced by global ones and vice
versa. ICT make global communication and world trade easier. ICT push ahead
globalisation, de-centralisation and flexibilisation of production, they are
a medium of the territorial restructuring of capitalism.
The
generation of networks of production that are typical for transnational corporations
has been made much easier by ICT, the latter are also a result of the economic
movements of restructuring that are typical for capital. ICT are not only medium
of globalisation processes, they are also a result of them. In order to optimize
the accumulation of capital, technologies have to increase their productivity.
This results in phases of heavy automation. ICT are a result of this. Globalisation
is a general process of mankind and also (in antagonistic forms) of capitalism
(see Fuchs/Hofkirchner 2000). The internationalisation of capital needs special
technologies. Historically shipping, railway, telegraph, telephone, radio, television
, automobile, aircraft, computer and nowadays ICT have been logical results
and functional categories of the international dimension of capitalism.
Concerning
modern ICT and computer-technologies, Marcuse’s arguments about technology are
very topical. On the one hand they promote the enslavement by the existing totality,
but they can also be used as a medium in processes of liberation. They are neither
value-free or neutral, nor liberating or enslaving as such. Hence utopias of
a free society should encompass ideas of how computer technologies could be
used in a free society in order to reach the realm of freedom and a maximum
of individual self-determination and free time. The generation of social prosperity
seem to be very easily accomplishable if we take a look at the powers of modern
technology, but whether we will really reach the realm of freedom is in no way
determined, maybe it is even questionable because the forestallment of social
change via the manipulation of consciousness is reaching new dimensions in the
information society. But what is important is that revolutionary social change
depends on the social self-organisation of revolutionary subjects and that this
is possible, even necessary in order to establish a socially and ecologically
sustainable society.
”The
technological processes of mechanization and standardization might release individual
energy into a yet uncharted realm of freedom beyond necessity [...] the individual
would be liberated from the work world’s imposing upon him alien needs and alien
possibilities. The
individual would be free to exert autonomy over a life that would be his own“
(Marcuse 1964: 2).
“Complete
automation in the realm of necessity would open the dimension of free time as
the one in which man’s private and social existence would constitute
itself. This would be the historical transcendence toward a new civilization”
(Marcuse 1964: 37).
Marcuse
says that technological society has to advance automation to the point where
the traditional relationship between labor time and free time is reversed and
free time becomes the individuals’ main occupation (Marcuse 1961: 46). The individual’s
freedom would be an autonomy from the apparatus of production and distribution
(Marcuse 1961: 56).
The
goal of the application of technology – which can not be realised in capitalism
– is the possibility of a satisfied existence. This would open up qualitatively
different relationships between human beings and between humans and nature (1964:
235). With the technological conquest of nature grows the conquest of man by
man (Marcuse 1964: 253).
The
historical alternative would be “the planned utilization of resources for the
satisfaction of vital needs with a minimum of toil, the transformation of leisure
into free time, the pacification of the struggle of existence“ (1964: 252f).
Marcuse says that the power to
freely dispose of one’s free time would be possible (Marcuse 1961: S. 41) and
that free time is part of a free society, spare time part of a repressive one
(Marcuse 1966b: 185).
The
development of modern technology, Marcuse says, has reached a point where the
overthrow of social relationships is necessary. Then sublation of labor by automation
would be possible: “Advanced industrial society is approaching the stage where
continued progress would demand the radical subversion of the prevailing direction
and organization of progress. This stage would be reached when material production
(including the necessary services) becomes automated to the extent that all
vital needs can be satisfied while necessary labor time is reduced to marginal
time. From this point on, technical progress would transcend the realm of necessity,
where it served as the instrument of domination and exploitation which thereby
limited its rationality; technology would become subject to the free play of
faculties in the struggle for the pacification of nature and of society” (Marcuse
1964: 16).
This
quotation again shows that Marcuse’s concept of technology is a dialectical
one. In capitalism technology is a means of domination and exploitation, in
a free society it enables man to reduce social necessary labor to a minimum
in order to establish a humane society.
Automation
is „incompatible with a society based on the private exploitation of human labor
power in the process of production“ (Marcuse 1964: S. 35) beruhenden Gesellschaft
nicht vereinbar. In capitalism the application of technology is antagonistic
and causes social problems.
Another
technology in another society would be part of a process of democratisation.
Labor would no longer mean exploitation, but self-development. The focus could
shift from material production to human self-realisation (Marcuse 1941: 316).
In Marxism, the view has sometimes been uttered that technology could be applied
in a new type of society in the way it is today. Marcuse on the contrary holds
the view that a qualitative change of society does not only encompass a qualitative
change of the economy and politics, also the “technological base” would have
to be transformed. Neither nationalisation nor socialisation would change the
rationality that lies at the foundation of modern technology. A new direction
of technological progress, the catastrophe of the existing one would be necessary,
not a quantitative development of the existing technological and scientific
rationality (Marcuse 1964: 227f).
Marcuse
says that if the working class liberates itself by a revolution, a society which
is no longer based on the principle „to each according to his work“, but which
relies on the principle „to each according to his needs“ is possible (Marcuse
1964: 41). Marcuse argues like Marx that in a first phase the new society still
has some characteristics of the old one, hence compulsion and wage labor are
not sublated fully. After a phase of construction the realm of freedom as a
second phase could be reached. Only in this second phase would quantitative
change (less wage labor, less domination etc.) result in qualitative one (no
wage labor, no domination etc.). In the realm of freedom a distribution of goods
that does not take into account the accomplished work of an individual and the
reduction of labor time to a minimum would be possible (Marcuse 1964: 44). We
will see that in prior writings Marcuse criticized the two phase-thesis of communism.
Existing
technology, Marcuse argues, is an instrument of destructive politics and hence
a qualitative change of politics would have to encompass the change of the direction
of technological progress. Politics would have to develop a new technology (Marcuse
1964: 227). “The technological transformation is at the same time political
transformation, but the political change would turn into qualitative social
change only to the degree to which it would alter the direction of technical
progress – that is, develop a new technology” (Marcuse 1964: 227). Marcuse says
that the completion of technological progress means the negation of existing
technology (Marcuse 1961: 65). But technology would not have to be renewed fully
because even today it makes possible the satisfaction of certain needs and the
reduction of hard work (ibid.: 242f). But a qualitative change of society would
also depend on the change of the technological base. The idea of qualitatively
different types of technological rationality would belong to a new historical
project (ibid.: 65f). A revolution would have to be a revolution against the
existing technocracy (Marcuse 1969: 288).
Another
technology in another society would mean technology as art that encompasses
the beautiful. Marcuse says that technology as art constructs the beautiful
as a type of a totality of life that encompasses society and nature. This would
be the opposite of the technology that dominates today’s repressive society
– a technology that has gotten rid of the destructive forces which are used
by man (Marcuse 1967: 80; see also Marcuse 1969: 261f).
All
of these considerations are very important for the discussion of the informatisation
and computerisation of labor. Since the microelectronical revolution, living
labor has been massively substituted by dead labor. Hence the objective presuppositions
of a jump into the realm of freedom seem to be very close, but subjectively
we seem to be miles away from it because technological rationality manipulates
consciousness massively and makes use of modern technologies. Some people work
longer and more intensive, whereas others do not work or have very precarious
jobs. Informatisation and computerisation as a medium and result of the crisis
of fordism change the world of labor heavily.
In Germany
the amount of the unemployed is 4 million, in france unemployment has been rising
from 1980 1,5 million to 1995 almost 3 millions. Only in the USA one can find
a decrease of absolute unemployment, but this has only been accomplished by
the massive expansion of precarious jobs. In 1994 2/3 of all jobs that were
created in the USA, were extremely bad paid, the reduction of unemployment has
also been achieved by the expansion of part time work. Manpower, a company that
relies mainly on part time work, is the largest employer in the USA (560.000
employees). In 1992, more than 34 million US-Americans worked in precarious
jobs. More than 25% of all US-employees have a temporary contract or one or
more part time jobs (all data from Rifkin 1995). All of this is a result of
strategies that want to raise profits by reducing labor costs. In most western
countries the increase of the wages has been much lower than the increase of
capital in the last two decades. The wage rates, i.e. the share of the wages
at the whole income of society, are falling below the level of the 1970ies.
The transitions
from Fordism to Postfordism, from Keynesianism to Neoliberalism and towards
an information-societal capitalism result in the widening of the global social
and ecological problems. Flexibilisation, de-centralisation, specialisation,
diversification, informatisation and the flattening of organisational structures
can be explained by the fact that capital is searching for new strategies and
areas of capital accumulation due to the lasting crisis. The transition from
Fordism to Postfordism took place in the framework of the search for a solution
of the crisis of Fordism and capital accumulation. Neoliberal politics aim at
creating a framework for the economy that makes it possible to raise profits
by minimizing the costs of investment (constant and variable capital). This
results in de-regulation, precarious job relationships, the dismantling of the
welfare state, deterioration of labor and social policies, lowering of taxes
on capital, flexible labor times, housewifezation etc.
The
new phase of economic globalisation and the creation of national states of competition
(Hirsch 1995) are also aspects of this restructuring of capitalism. The outsourcing
of production which allows a reduction of the constant and variable share of
capital is a result of it. The restructuring of corporations (de-centralisation,
flexibilisation, outsourcing, lean management, flattening of hierarchies, just-in-time-production
etc.) does not mean a humanisation of labor, its aim is increasing profits by
cutting costs. The model for this is the Japanese Lean-Production-system of
Toyota, hence one also quite often speaks of Toyotism. „The
basic purpose of the Toyota production system is to increase profits by reducing
costs - that is, by completely eliminating waste such as excessive stocks or
workforce“ (Monden 1983, S. 11). As new qualities of the mode of discipline
(see Fuchs 2001) the society of control (Deleuze 1993) emerges. This refers
to the ideological integration of the work-force; motivation, identification,
bonus-systems, share options, team work, flat hierarchies etc. All of these
strategies are employed in order to increase profits and productivity. On the
one hand we are witnessing different types of participative management, on the
other hand a re-taylorisation of labor takes place. Technological changes involve
the usage of flexible machineries of production, a transition from standardised
mass production to diversified quality production with a small amounts of produced
commodities which have a high quality. The goal of automation and computerisation
is the decrease of labor costs in order to increase profits.
The usage
of modern ICT in organisations is due to economic interests. Without the global
crisis of Fordism, the new technological paradigm would also have emerged sooner
or later, but this process would have taken place much slower. The massive diffusion
of ICT results from capitalism’s permanent search for effective means of production,
rationalisation and mechanisation. ICT make outsourcing and de-centralisation
of production, team work, the flexibilisation of jobs and the flattening of
organisational hierarchies much easier. These new technologies are a logical
result of the development of the productive forces. Unqualified and hence highly
mechanised jobs mainly in the areas of electronics and textile production have
been massively outsourced from Western countries to Southeast Asia during the
last 20 years.
This has
resulted in sweat shops with very inhumane conditions of labor. Marxist feminism
stressed that the over-exploitation of women in these sweat shops has to do
with ICT, economic globalisation, an international division of labor and housewifezation.
Economic globalisation and the third industrial revolution would only be possible
by the exploitation of women in the Third World (see e.g. Mies 1996).
Marcuses’
indications that technology takes on an inhumane character in capitalism, also
prove to be true in the Information Society. But the widening of the global
problems and the precarious living conditions of large parts of the world population
are not due to immanent features of technology as such. All of this is a result
of the capitalist application of technology. An immediate transition into the
realm of freedom would be possible today.
Robert
Kurz and the Krisis-group stress legitimately that the ontologisation of labor
has been a negative feature of traditional marxism and the soviet system. Labor
has been fetishised and idealised. Labor and laborer were considered something
like religion and god in the soviet system (see Kurz 1991: 11-15, Kurz 1994).
The goal was the liberation of labor from its capitalist ties, not the liberation
from labor itself and the compulsions that result from it. Labor society would
reach its own limits today, hence it would be necessary to advance to a system
that goes beyond labor. Krisis wants labor to be sublated, and along with it
bourgeois society. They call for a social movement against labor (Krisis 1999:
41).
Indeed,
today the goal of progressive forces should not be the liberation of labor from
its capitalist wrap, labor and full time employment for all, but a right to
laziness (Lafargue 1899), the establishment of a realm of freedom, free time
instead of labor, mental instead of material labor, holiday instead of labor
day, non-operational thinking instead of instrumental reason, solidarity instead
of the war of competition, sensuousness instead of repression and freedom as
a permanent state as well as the end of material and psychological shortages.
This could result in a society in which individuals co-operate with a high degree
of solidarity and where they have the highest degree of self-realisation and
well-rounded development (in the sense of Marx). Marcuse’s utopia of a free
society is still extremely important today.
But,
and these are my greatest concerns, it is still the case that change of the
existing direction of progress would mean fundamental change, but social change
presupposes that there are vital needs for it as well as the experience of intolerable
relationships. In the society we live in, these needs and experiences are forestalled
by a large apparatus of manipulation (Marcuse 1965: 125).
Here
he speaks of humans as the potential main productive force of revolution who
can put their consciousness and practice outside of the system, they can transcend
the existing false totality and work towards its sublation. The “Keimform” (germ)
of a new society does not so much cover social structures for Marcuse, but emancipatory
human consciousness which unfortunately seems to be absorbed more and more into
the inside of the system in the advanced industrial society.
Just
like Marcuse, I think that the material base of a society must have reached
a certain development, so that such an emancipatory outside can lead us into
the realm of freedom. In various discussions it is today often argued that a
material and economic type of outside exists (e.g. self-managed corporations,
Linux, circles of exchange etc.). Nonetheless I pretty much favour Marcuse’s
position which holds that economic processes are part of the inner dynamics
of capitalism and that self-organising political movements that want to establish
a new society and rely on direct democracy concerning their own organisational
principles tend to organise themselves and their consciousness on the outside
of the existing totality. It is not idealistic to say that critical consciousness
is part of the outside of society. Subjectivity is an important factor of the
dialectics of subject and object as pointed out by Marx and Marcuse (see Marcuse
1966c). The inner contradictions of society and the productive forces develop
objectively, but there is not an automated development towards a society that
is socially and ecologically sustainable.
Emancipatory
subjects with class consciousness are necessary. It is not determined whether
such a consciousness can be developed today and to which outcome struggles that
result from it will lead. Marcuse says that the material and intellectual productive
forces that are entangled into the existing antagonisms are ready to enter a
higher type of social existence by conscious struggles with the existing forces.
The outcome depends on the conditions and possibilities of these struggles and
on consciousness that develops from it. A necessary stipulation would be that
the subjects become conscious of their slavery and the reasons of it, that they
see liberation as something necessary and that they try to find ways towards
it (Marcuse 1996c).
For
Marcuse these arguments encompass the view that existing technologies can not
simply be overtaken into a new society, but many new qualities would have to
be developed in order to reach the realm of freedom. “The
technological transformation is at the same time political transformation, but
the political change would turn into qualitative social change only to the degree
to which it would alter the direction of technical progress – that is, develop
a new technology” (Marcuse 1964: 227)
In
the 1930ies the Critical Theory of the Frankfurt School supposed that a social
revolution and a transition into a new society would soon come. With the rise
of German fascism this assessment proved to be wrong. Marcuse, Horkheimer, Adorno
and others were hence in many respects disillusioned by the working class as
a revolutionary subject. Whereas Horkheimer and Adorno now supposed that revolutionary
change would not be possible for a long time, because consciousness in the advanced
industrial society would necessarily be false consciousness, Marcuse
remained much more optimistic. On the one hand he also argued that qualitative
social change is forestalled by manipulation and social controls, but he did
not totalise this view. He said that besides this tendency there are still potential
revolutionary subjects. He also was in search for the outside of society and
was much closer to a unity of revolutionary theory and practice than Horkheimer
and Adorno who saw the prevention of a second Auschwitz as the only possible
and necessary political goal.
One
of the main questions in sociology is how structures and actions are related.
In classical sociology this question has been solved in reductionist manner.
Functionalism (e.g. Durkheim, Merton, Parsons, Luhmann) and Structuralism (e.g.
Althusser, Balibar) solved this problem in favour of social structures, Theory
of Action and Symbolic Interactionism (e.g. Weber, Mead, Habermas) in favour
of individual and social actions. The shortcomings of these approaches can be
avoided by a dialectical approach that takes into account that social structures
constrain and manipulate individual thinking and acting and that these structures
are being changed by social actions. Marcuse realised this dialectical relationship.
On the one hand he stressed that the social structures of late capitalism produce
false consciousness in tremendous amounts, on the other hand he also stressed
the possibilities of revolutionary change. He
e.g. said in the opening words of his One Dimensional-Man: “One-Dimensional
Man will vacillate throughout between two contradictory hypotheses: (1) that
advanced industrial society is capable of containing qualitative change for
the foreseeable future; (2) that forces and tendencies exist which may break
this containment and explode the society. I do not think that a clear answer
can be given” (Marcuse 1964: xlvii)
Already
Marx had considered this relationships as a dialectical one as can be shown
e.g. by the following quotation: “Men make their own history, but they do not
make it as they please; they do not make it under self-selected circumstances,
but under circumstances existing already, given and transmitted from the past”
(Marx 1852: 115). Not only structures and actions – to which revolutionary thinking
and acting always has to refer – are mediated dialectically, there is also a
specific dialectic of liberation as Marcuse pointed out. He says that there
is no revolution without individual liberation and no liberation of the individual
without the liberation of society (Marcuse 1969: 54).
At
the time of the students’ revolt, some students squatted Adorno’s Institute
for Social Research in order to force him to position himself. Adorno thought
he had been misunderstood, he did not see it the way that the time for revolution
had come and he did not want to be some type of leader or father figure. The
second point surely was true, but the consequences – the eviction of the institute
by the police which had been called by Adorno – was in all respects wrong. Later,
this was also pointed out by Marcuse who wrote in a letter to Adorno that this
had been very brutal, that he is with the students when the alternative is one
between the police and left students. He said that representatives of the Critical
Theory had to face the fact that these students had been influenced by them
and that he was very happy about this fact (see Behrens 2000: 123f).
Marcuse
differed from Horkheimer and Adorno in the respect that practical aspects of
politics were always very important for him. Whereas one could get the impression
from One Dimensional Man (which was originally published in 1964) that manipulation
totally dominates society (there are only some slight comments about liberation
and the possibilities of a “great refusal”), Marcuse seems to be very impressed
by the students’ revolt and the emergence of the New Left in his Essay on Liberation
(1969). A radical potential for liberation and emancipatory practice at once
seemed to be very topical. Marcuse was an “intransigent optimist, always on
the search for new social movements of liberation. His main interest is not
to trace out revolutionary prophecies, but the historical possibilities of a
revolution and the deep-rooted human need for ‘another society’” (Heinz Lubasz
in Marcuse et al. 1978: 138). The dialectic of structures and actions also shows
us that a critical theory of society has to consider revolutionary change. Marcuse
always thought that revolution is a possibility and that it is necessary to
liberate humankind. Young Marcuse wrote about the necessity of the catastrophic
sublation of the factual condition by total revolution (Marcuse 1932). This
motive remained a central one during his entire life.
At
the end of the 1960ies Marcuse was very impressed by the revolts of the students,
of the people in the ghettos and in the Third World which made the theme of
liberation a topical one (see Marcuse 1969 and 1972). He said that they have
revoked the idea of revolution from the continuum of suppression and have connected
it with its true dimension – the one of liberation (Marcuse 1969: 243). Marcuse
(1972) is also impressed by the protest of the emerging ecological-, civil rights-
and feminist-movements. Another time he said that a political feminist movement
means the negation of the existing values and goals of patriarchal society and
hence also the negation of the values and goals of capitalism
(Marcuse 1973/74: 170). The new groups would not automatically be subjects
of revolution, but Marcuse considered them as anticipating groups which could
function as catalysts for revolution (Marcuse et al. 1978: 57). The working
class would be necessary for a revolution, but today it would be part of the
stabilisation of the existing order and it could be characterised by its false
consciousness (see Marcuse 1969: 155, 285f). Objectively, Marcuse considered
the working class revolutionary as such, but in late capitalism it is not subjectively
revolutionary for itself. Marcuse said that consciousness and practice of the
working class had become bourgeois (Marcuse et al. 1978: 56).
The
technological changes would also transform the working class, the classical
blue collar-workers are substituted by white collar-employees and an increasing
importance of mental activities in the area of production. As such this would
make the blowing up of the existing order much easier, but in fact the “new
working class” would be very integrated and adapted to the system (Marcuse 1969:
286f). Marcuse says that the working class does not simply have to loose its
chain in advanced industrial society, a fact that also has theoretical consequences.
Marx’ category of class is defined by the role in the process of production,
but the capitalist process of production has changed the social existence and
consciousness of the exploited by intensifying and generalising exploitation
and increasing productivity. Quantity (a higher level of wealth) results in
new qualities (bourgeois consciousness, bourgeois needs) (Marcuse 1974: 135).
Opposition
moves from the organised working class to struggling minorities. A new subject
of historical change emerges. A first necessary step of a revolution is a radical
change of consciousness (Marcuse 1969: 285). Marcuse says that such consciousness
showed up and that it had anticipating, designing qualities that are open and
ready for the new radical and extravagant prospects of freedom (Marcuse 1968:
73). The objective human factor of revolution, Marcuse says, can be found in
the working class which is powerless and kept quiet, whereas the subjective
revolutionary political consciousness is established by the nonconformist young
intellectuals and the non-privileged parts of the inhabitants of the Third World.
This would show that a movement that aims at radical change can come into existence
outside of the working class, but it would have to try to activate the suppressed
forces of rebellion within the labor forces (Marcuse 1968: 73).
What
is necessary in the view of Marcuse is radical enlightenment by developing the
consciousness (and unconsciousness) of the exploited. This could result in needs
that go beyond the violence of the enslaving existing ones (1969: 288) and could
only be done by a radical left that engages in political education (Marcuse
1972: 35) and that tries to translate spontaneous protest into organised actions
(1972: 52). This would not necessarily mean an authoritarian elite and political
leaders, but the possibility of a revolutionary avant-garde (Marcuse 1973/74:
164). The non-conformity of the
new opposition is shown by its unorthodox behaviours that do not accept traditional
political practices like parties and committees. Marcuse says that these rebels
do not care about things that politicians, representatives or candidates say
(1969: 293). The direct actions employed could be seen as being direct democratic
and they would anticipate the extensive democratisation of the existing totalitarian
society. What would be necessary is a revolutionary power that puts an end to
existing violence and that builds up a socialist society. Some examples of such
actions would be an unlimited general strike, the simultaneous squatting and
over-taking of corporations, government offices, centers of information and
traffic (Marcuse 1972: 58). But Marcuse also warned of counter-productive actions
like aimless destruction that help to organise the people against the Left.
He
saw counter-institutions as necessary, e.g. radical, free media (1972: 60).
For the establishment of institutions that are critical of the system money
would have to be raised (1973/75: 175). The disintegration of social morality,
Marcuse argues, shows itself e.g.
in the breakdown of work discipline, working slowly, an increase of disobedience
towards rules, wild strikes, boycotts and insubordination (1969: 310). But this
would not automatically result in a revolution, but Marcuse saw it as a symptom
of crisis. Nonetheless the system could be held up by employing violence and
totalitarian controls. Marcuse sympathised with the New Left, but nonetheless
criticised it heavily (e.g. its anti-intellectualism and its missing of an extensive
theoretical perspective). His disillusionment about the working class decreased
a little bit due the fact that at the end of the 1960ies the amount of strikes,
sabotage and refusals of work increased in western countries (but this vanished
soon). In Counterrevolution and Revolt (1972), Marcuse was impressed by this
rebellion against the whole of forced conditions and the system of performance
as such (1972: 28).
Marcuse
argued that in late capitalism a sharpening
of protests, locally and regionally organised, would be possible and he said
that maybe some corporations could break out of the system, a radicalisation
of self-management would be possible which could result in a diffuse disintegration
of the system that intensifies itself (Marcuse et al. 1978: 61). The revolts
that took place at the end of the 60ies and the beginning of the 70ies have
not lead to a revolution. Marcuse did not expect a revolution, he said that
this would only be one possibility, presupposed that an extensive movement emerges
that also covers the working class. Such a possibility is always given, but
it presupposes the extensive organisation of revolutionary consciousness. And
this was not accomplished by the New Left. So it is not only the fault of those
forces that adapt their consciousness to the system.
Marcuse’s
view of a dialectical embededness of revolutionary process into the relationships
of social structures and actions is still very topical. Today not only the working
class is becoming bourgeois, this also holds for protest movements who argue
and act less and less revolutionary. Nonetheless due to the widening of the
global problems, revolutionary subjects would be necessary. The task of the
unity of political theory and practice in this situation is to trigger revolutionary
consciousness and the self-organisation of potential subjects. Hence a left-wing
avant-garde is still necessary, as already pointed out by Herbert Marcuse 25
years ago. It is even indispensable if we want to advance towards a new society.
Elsewhere
I have explained processes of class structuring in Postfordism at some detail
(see Fuchs 2001: 111-123). Let me summarise some aspects: Capital and labor
power are contradictory parts of a class relationship because workers perform
unpaid surplus labor. The accumulation of capital needs an ever growing and
permanent increase of surplus value that is produced. Reproductive workers (who
are in most cases women) are exploited in the framework of patriarchal modes
of production (which mostly are located in families) by capital and men because
they perform unpaid or very low paid labor which is necessary for the existence
and permanent reproduction of capitalism. Wage laborers exploit reproductive
workers in order to have the physical and psychological abilities that enable
them to be exploited by capital. The
decreasing number of core workers[2] can only keep up
its full time wage-relationships because capital tries to worsen the working
conditions of peripheral laborers (part time jobs, seasonal work, precarious
jobs etc.)[3].
The over-exploited peripheral laborers form an own class that is exploited by
capital. Core workers quite frequently engage themselves in this relationship
of domination on the side of capital by promoting non-solidarity and their own
advantages at the expense of others.
Workers
in racist relationships of production are also over-exploited by capital. Over-
or Super-exploitation means that capital creates peripheral, patriarchal and
racist relationships (which can be seen as colonies of primitive accumulation)
in order to maximize the production of profit by deregulating the conditions
of labor and minimizing the variable share of capital. Core- and peripheral
laborers (as well as the unemployed) frequently support the maintenance of racist
relationships of domination because they hope that their situation improves
if the social situation of others gets worse. Hence those who are exploited
in racist manners form an own class which is part of a relationship of exploitation
in which capital and other promoters of racism form the antagonistic part.
Another
class relationship exists between center and periphery of capitalism because
on the one hand the world market creates poverty in the Third World and on the
other hand the export of capital results in the production of surplus value
in the peripheral areas which is transferred to the centers. Capitalism is in
need of milieus of primitive accumulation that are super-exploited and ostracized
in order to produce surplus value, to guarantee capital accumulation and the
permanent reproduction of capitalism. Patriarchal and racist modes of production,
peripheral laborers and the peripheral areas of the capitalist world system
can be regarded as such milieus of primitive accumulation. These class relationships
are coined by an asymmetrical distribution of power, exploitation and domination.
Asymmetrical power also means the asymmetrical access to information. More powerful
groups have better access to information and knowledge.
These
processes of class structuring that are typical for Postfordism result in various
potential revolutionary subjects which find themselves placed at the less powerful
side of the dividing lines of society: the working class, reproductive laborers,
feminist movements, peripheral workers, the unemployed, the racially exploited,
anti-racist-movements, the poor, Third World-solidarity movements. In addition
we find protest movements such as the ecology movement, civil rights movements,
the youth movement, the alternative movement, the homosexual- and transgender-movement
and the peace movement. Processes of class structuration are no longer solely
determined by the process of production because the amount of those who immediately
produce surplus value decreases due to the effects of automation. This does
not result in a transition to a classless society, on the contrary: exploitation,
the forestallment of social change and powerlessness reach new dimensions.
Political
globalisation is influenced by the existing antagonisms of capitalism, but it
can also be understood (as Deleuze and Guattari (1977) pointed out) as the emergence
of emancipatory social networks whose parts establish alternative perspectives
against neo-liberalism and the globally existing precarious conditions of life.
This could result in a large movement that sublates the existing totality of
society. In Fuchs (2001), I argued that the emergence and self-organisation
of revolutionary social networks can with reference to Gilles Deleuze and Félix
Guattari be described as rhizomes. I pointed out that the emergence of rhizomes
should be seen in the context of the theory of self-organisation. We can not
assume that social movements automatically have an emancipatory character. They
are only potential revolutionary subjects and hence it is possible that they
develop needs and abilities that go beyond the existing totality, structures
of self-organisation and a practice that is critical of society. But these qualities
do no form the essence of social movements. Some of these movements can already
be characterised by some aspects that are typical for processes of emancipation
(such as direct democratic types of organisation, autonomy, self-organisation),
but this does not mean that they can already be considered as revolutionary
subjects.
The
question of an intellectual avant-garde is again very important today. Rhizomes
and meta-rhizomes do not automatically have revolutionary consciousness that
goes beyond capitalism; and hence intellectual avant-gardes are necessary in
order to trigger the self-organisation of rhizomes. Such intellectual avant-gardes
do not want to be leaders of a revolution such as the traditional marxist-leninist
parties and they try to trigger the transformation off potential revolutionary
subjects into real revolutionary subjects who see their problems as those of
others and those of others as their own ones. An intellectual avant-garde is
not at the head of revolution as a leading and steering force, it only triggers
revolution. Marcuse would have had quite similar views because he attached no
value to the classical leninist avant-garde (for the conception of an intellectual
avant-garde see also Fuchs 2001: pp 160ff).
Networked,
revolutionary social movements do not need to have homogenous interests and
they do not have to aim at an homogenisation of their politics in order to establish
a common political perspective. On the other hand they also do not have to tolerate
all possible political options, this would result in a postmodern “anything
goes” that can simply destroy revolutionary movements. It makes sense that on
the one hand they stress their different political ideas and strategies, their
specific local and regional conditions of political struggle and that they on
the other hand also develop a common perspective by stressing what unites them
in their struggles. Steven Best and Douglas Kellner (1997) have characterised
such a political strategy as a synthesis of modern and post-modern politics.
They say that a unity of aspects from “modern politics” such as solidarity,
alliances, consensus, universal rights, macro-politics and of aspects from “postmodern
politics” such as difference, plurality, multi-perspectiveness, identity and
micro-politics is necessary. Such a dialectic of modernism and postmodernism
could help in solving the global problems. A position of unity in diversity
has also been formulated by Fuchs/Hofkirchner (2000) for the political as well
as for the cultural area. The future of our society depends on the self-organisation
and radicalisation of existing protest movements which are quite bourgeois nowadays.
The central concept of all of this is self-organisation.
The theory
of self-organisation (see Fuchs 2001) has resulted in a change of scientific
paradigms: a shift from the Newtonian paradigm to the approaches of complexity
has taken place. We are going from predictability to deterministic chaos, from
order and stability to instability, chaos and dynamics; from certainty and determination
to risk, ambiguity and uncertainty; from the control and steering to the self-organisation
of systems, from linearity to complexity and multidimensional causality; from
reductionism to emergentism, from being to becoming and from fragmentation to
interdisciplinarity. This has been interpreted as a shift from modern to post-modern
knowledge (Best/Kellner 1997). The Social Sciences are still dominated by the
Newtonian paradigm: methodologically systematic and precise empirical investigations
followed by inductive generalisations dominate instead of the ascending from
the abstract to the concrete as proposed by Marx in the introduction to the
Grundrisse (Marx 1857/58); traditionally the social sciences have been fragmented
into anthropology, economics, political science and sociology and there is a
lack of interdisciplinarity. Still social scientists’ main concern is to discover
universal rules that fully explain individual and social actions and that make
it possible to plan and predict the development of society. Such views do not
take into account the dialectics of generality and particularity and of chance
and necessity that are suggested by the sciences of complexity. A further flaw
of classical approaches within the social sciences has been that human history
has been conceived as inevitably progressive. Personally I think that during
phases of instability and crises we find points where the further development
of history is not determined, but relatively open. Such points again and again
show up, but it is not determined how the outcome will look like. They are an
expression of antagonistic forces that lead to social crises and instabilities.
Immanuel Wallerstein says that the social sciences are confronted with an end
of certainties today, irreversibility, chance and non-predictability are very
important today (see Wallerstein 1995, 1997).
Hence it
is not determined how the society of tomorrow will look like. There are many
possibilities, in a phase of turbulence and instability the further development
of the system can not be predicted. An ideal type of society can not be planned
and the evolution of society can not be steered in a pre-determined manner.
But we can work out some principles that could increase the chance that we will
not face ultimate destruction and that we can establish a society that is socially
and economically sustainable. And also in this respect I believe that social
self-organisation and self-determination are very important; these are principles
that could replace hierarchic modes of organisation. Self-organisation always
means a direct-democratic bottom-up-process. I believe that the historical evolution
of society has reached a point of bifurcation where massive instabilities show
up which result in the worsening of the global problems and where the further
development of society is relatively open. So we face an ambivalence of great
risks and dangers on the one hand, but of great possibilities on the other.
There are several possible scenarios of development: The end of humanity due
to an escalation of the global problems, the further crisis-ridden reproduction
of capitalism in the framework of an extremely militarised and repressive regime,
a transition towards openly fascist types of capitalism or fundamental social
change that presupposes a change of attitudes in all areas of society and that
can help us in establishing socially and ecologically sustainable paths of development.
I consider only the last alternative as a desirable one.
Concerning the future development of society,
I am not too optimistic. But the evolution of society is not independent from
social actions. In a phase of societal instability and chaos the intervention
of humans is very important. It is not possible to steer further developments,
but maybe evolution can be guided into certain paths by applying sustainable
principles of social systems design. I.e., human intervention enables us to
increase the possibility that a certain path of development will be taken; but:
we will never have certainty. If the intervention of humans into society and
nature continues to rely on destruction and exploitation, it seems quite obvious
to me that the result will be one of the first three alternatives that I lined
out and that I am horrified of. But if the potential of self-organisation can
be activated – i.e. if we try to work against social hierarchies and injustice
by making use of direct democratic bottom-up-interventions –, I am quite confident
that the outcome will be the fourth scenario and that we will humanise the conditions
of life globally by relying on the principles of self-organisation, self-management
and self-determination in all areas of social life. A society that is socially
as well as ecologically sustainable could result from this.
I
still have certain hopes that the new social movements will play an important
part in the democratisation of society because direct democracy and self-organisation
have in some respects always been important for them. But on the one hand we
are witnessing the institutionalisation and hence the potential end of social
protest movements today, on the other hand what these movements are missing
is an overall and extensive perspective that covers the solidarity and bonds
of all people who are exploited or suppressed as well as self-organisation as
an extensive principle of self-organisation in the economy, politics and all
other areas of life. The Internet mainly is a medium of attaining profits. But
modern ICT can also be used by self-organising political movements in order
to act in a more networked and effective manner. There are some examples that
show that the self-organisation of critical and oppositional actions can be
supported by networking (see Fuchs 2001). ICT are part of those structures that
keep up slavery and misery, but they also pose possibilities that should be
used in order to effectively support the self-organisation of critical movements
(see Fuchs 2001). But also in this area we do not (yet?) find a potential that
is large enough for fundamental social change.
In
our near future we will find a radically transformed society (or no society
at all, but this also means radical transformations) and this society in transition
will be characterised by large social unrest and an increase of daily violence
during the next decades. It is not the question if we want to change society
because it changes permanently. The question that poses itself is if we want
an escalation of the global problems or if we want to change society and humankind
in a positive sense. The grand crisis of the world system that we are witnessing
today is a result of the antagonisms of capitalist development. The crisis is
relatively independent from the will of the individuals, but this is not true
for the possible developments in a point of historical bifurcation. In such
a phase or crisis, instability and chaos small political actions can have great
consequences. This is also known as the butterfly-effect. Hence the free will
is very important in such situations. Progress is possible, but certainly not
inevitable, and it depends on social self-organisation and on a social practice
that triggers the transition towards humane paths of history.
These aspects
of self-organisation have been anticipated by Herbert Marcuse although he did
not know the theory of self-organisation which at these times was still in its
infancy. He described the fact that in revolutionary situations small causes
can result in large effects as domino-effect: Rebellions that start at certain
locations could increase and intensify themselves (Marcuse 1966b: 176). Marcuse
says that if a revolution is successful in a strategically important country,
it could enlarge itself to other countries and regions like some kind of snowball
system (Marcuse 1973/74: 148). The theory of self-organisation stresses that
during phases of instability where initial fluctuations intensify themselves,
small perturbations can trigger large processes of self-organisation. Concerning
the revolutionary process, Marcuse spoke of groups that are very weak in the
beginning and can catalyze larger rebellions (Marcuse 1969: 284). Elsewhere
I have described the self-reinforcement and –amplification of social movements
as Temporary Autonomous Rhizomes (TAR) (Fuchs 2001). Marcuse also speaks of
such de-centralised, potentially revolutionary types of (self-)organisation.
The process of inner disintegration could take on a more far-reaching, de-centralised,
diffused and spontaneous character, it could take place at several places at
the same time or could spread itself. But local dis-functionalities and disturbances
could only become core zones of social change if they are organised politically
(Marcuse 1969: 48).
Marcuse
also stressed that the development is relatively open in phases of crisis. He
says that the future only means the possibility of liberation and that the latter
is not the only possibility, there could also be a long period of “civilised”
barbarity with or without nuclear destruction (Marcuse 1969: 314). Social self-organisation
also means that a revolutionary theory needs theory and critical consciousness,
but it does not need leaders who organise all of this. What is needed is the
triggering of true consciousness and critical thinking, that is all. Spontaneity
is an expression of the self-organisation of revolutionary movements that could
lead us towards a new society. Such rebellions, Marcuse says, resist centralised
bureaucratic-communist organisation as well as pseudo-democratic liberal ones.
A strong element of spontaneity and anarchism would be part of rebellious movements
(Marcuse 1969: 315). Enlightenment, education and political practice are – as
Marcuse points out in the same passage – necessary. Not as a leading force,
but as a trigger of self-organisation. Self-organising revolutionary movements
anticipate a society that is based on the principle of self-determination. Marcuse
says that the gratification of vital material needs by the revolution must be
accomplished in accordance with this principle (Marcuse 1973/74: 171). He regarded
the Great Refusal and the direct democratic types of revolutionary actions that
I mentioned, as types of self-organisation. And this could result in a situation
where the conditions have reached a point where the take-over of single plants
and corporations and the self-organisation of labor can take place (ibid.: 173).
The
material conditions have reached a level today where an immediate transition
into the realm of freedom would be possible. But due to the capitalist types
of socialisation the development of the productive forces has resulted in a
permanent crisis. The general-self-organisational, antagonistic evolution of
capitalism is crisis-ridden, the antagonism between the productive forces and
the relationships of production manifests itself in massive ways nowadays. Social
self-organisation is necessary in order to increase the possibility that we
will reach sustainable paths of development.
The establishment
of a sustainable and socially self-organised society needs revolutionary, self-organising
subjects who develop critical consciousness and make use of it in social struggles.
It is not certain whether or not this consciousness can be developed and what
outcome struggles that result from it will have. Marcuse said that the productive
forces that are entangled into the existing antagonisms would be ready for a
higher type of existence. The outcome would depend on the conditions of social
struggles and of consciousness that develops itself in these struggles. This
would also have to encompass subjects who have understood the reasons for their
slavery, want liberation and have realized ways towards it (Marcuse 1966c).
This is the main aspect of processes of social self-organisation in society
today.
People
would recognise themselves in their commodities, they find their soul in their
automobile, hi-fi set, split-level home, kitchen equipment (Marcuse 1964: 9).
By manipulating the minds with the help of technology, mass media and commodities,
one-dimensional thinking and acting emerges: “Thus emerges a pattern of one-dimensional
thought and behavior in which ideas, aspirations, and objectives that, by
their content, transcend the established universe of discourse and action are
either repelled or reduced to terms of this universe“ (Marcuse 1964: 12).
Also
language is one-dimensional in late capitalism. Attributes such as “freedom”,
“equality” and “democracy” are taken in order to characterise capitalism (free
market, initiative, election etc.). This skips that the prevailing mode way
of freedom is servitude and the prevailing mode of equality superimposed inequality
(Marcuse 1964: 88). Public and personal opinion accepts manipulation. Language
and communication immunise themselves against the articulation of protest and
refusal. Commercials impose new meanings and images on commodities in order
to sell them. Critical thinking shall be suppressed, only stupid, reflex-like
reactions of the objects of commercials are welcomed. Commercials make use of
an antagonistic, manipulating language, it creates new words in order to sell
commodities.
Dominating
forces present brutalities as something very normal that should not be questioned.
E.g. commercials of the Civil Defense Headquaters talk about a “’deluxe fallout-shelter’
with wall-to-wall carpeting (“soft“), lounge chairs, television, and Scrabble,
‚designed as a combination family room during peacetime and family fallout shelter
should war break out’“ (Marcuse 1964: 248).
Marcuse
argues that today language is a one-dimensional one, one that is a vehicle of
streamlining consciousness. An antipode would be a dialectical language that
speaks about antagonisms. Marx e.g. speaks about the proletarians in his Communist
Manifesto to whom he gives the attributes of total oppression and of the total
defeat of oppression (Marcuse 1964: 119). People are manipulated in such ways
that they accept and tolerate capitalism. This means false consciousness that
could be transformed into a true one. False needs, Marcuse says, are such that
are imposed by social forces in order to keep up suppression. Hence these needs
are also repressive ones. “Most of the prevailing needs to relax, to have fun,
to behave and consume in accordance with the advertisements, to love and hate
what others love and hate, belong to this category of false needs” (Marcuse
1964: 5). As long as people are manipulated and do not have autonomous self-consciousness,
the answers to the question what true and false needs are can not be understood
as being their own ones.
The
controls executed by society are reproduced in the individual’s consciousness.
Marcuse calls this process introjection (Marcuse 1964: 10). “The result is,
not adjustment but mimesis: an immediate identification of the individual
with his society and, through it, with society as a whole“ (ibid.: 10).
Marcuse says that repressive tolerance is a typical phenomenon of bourgeois
society today (Marcuse 1965c). Tolerance is pretended in order to suppress alternative
social developments. Predominating ideas and attitudes as well as alternative
views are tolerated in order to protect the already existing machinery of discrimination
(Marcuse 1965c: 139). In the affluent society there is plenty of discussion,
all possible standpoints can be heard. It is always assumed that the people
are able to select from these ideas autonomously based on a free understanding.
But exactly this is what Marcuse questions. He says that domination by the monopolised
media which are instruments of economic and political power produces a mentality
that relies on predetermined views of what is right and wrong, true and false.
Hence departures from the “common sense” are blocked, everything that does not
belong to the establishment is not accepted. This starts with the language that
is published and ordained. There is a strict stabilisation of the sense that
words make. Rational discussion and the persuasion of the contrary are almost
impossible. Other words can be spoken and heard, but the conservative majority
assesses them instantly and automatically in specific predetermined manners
(Marcuse 1965c: 146). Hence the decisions on opposed view are predetermined,
the toleration of opposite views is mere illusion, the
reality means repressive suppression of true consciousness by the effective
and subtle production of a one-dimensional mass consciousness. Hence modern
democracy, Marcuse says, is a totalitarian democracy. The individuals would
not even have the want to read, see or hear something that does not go along
with the generally accepted truth resp. falsity (Marcuse 1973/74: 152). Bourgeois
democracy has a militant and reactionary character but is accepted by the people
(ibid.: 160).
Marcuse
says that capitalism is a totalitarian system. Totalitarianism is not only a
terrorist political co-ordination of society, it is also a non-terrorist economic-technological
co-ordination that manipulates needs according to economical interests and that
hence also forestalls opposition against the interest organised by the whole
(Marcuse 1961: 57). But nonetheless bourgeois democracy is something qualitatively
different from fascism for Marcuse because it poses better possibilities for
a transition to socialism. Hence Marcuse defended bourgeois democracy when it
was necessary although he was one of its hardest critics. During the time of
German fascism he drew up studies for the Office of War Information (OWI) and
the Office of Strategic Services (OSS) about this system, the mentality of the
Germans and strategies that should be applied in order to defeat fascism. Here
his goal was the establishment of bourgeois democracy instead of the fascist
system, not because he liked western democracy, but because in such a system
there are beside all totalitarian aspects some basic rights which result in
better conditions for political struggles than in fascist systems.
If
democracy means self-determination of the people, i.e. a political system where
everyone can participate in those processes of decision-making that effect him
or her with an equal distribution of power, then it becomes very clear that
capitalist society is – as Marcuse stressed – only a pseudo-democracy. Totalitarian
aspects dominate in all social sub systems, this is also true for today’s post-fordist
phase of capitalism. Let us take a short look at the exclusions and totalitarianisms
that constitute bourgeois society today. This will show us that Marcuse’s assessments
are still true.
Capitalism
is based on various asymmetries and exclusive social information[4] in economics, politics
and culture. First, there are asymmetries concerning the economic resources.
Private owners and capitalists exclusively control resources and the means of
production. Economic information in capitalism means exclusive economic information
that is made possible by the private control of the means of production and
extensive landed property. The production of surplus value and other relationships
of production that depend on the principles of mastery and exploitation and
include a transfer of quanta of living labour from exploited groups to exploiters,
are compulsory for those who are excluded from the control of economic information.
A labourer “is free in the double sense, that
as a free man he can dispose of his labour-power as his own commodity, and that
on the other hand he has no other commodity for sale, is short of everything
necessary for the realisation of his labour-power” (Marx 1867). He/She does
not own the means of productions and what (s)he produces and (s)he is forced
to sell her/his labour power. Wage and reproductive labour are necessary for
the production of surplus value and are constitutive for the formation of class
relationships. Class relationships are characterised by domination and exploitation.
The exploited work more than they are being paid for, they perform unpaid surplus
labour or they even (have to) work for free. Concerning the distribution of
the surplus products and the commodities produced, it can be said that they
are not being owned by those who produce them. The immediate producers and the
ones that are indirectly exploited by capital only get a minimum share.
House and reproductive labour are necessary for
the production of capital and the reproduction of labour power. This is a type
of unpaid or very low paid labour; capitalism and the production of value could
not exist without it. This type of labour is mostly done by women and in our
patriarchal society there are essentialistic, biologistic naturalisation that
define reproductive labour as belonging to the “nature” of women. Female minds
and bodies are controlled, used and exploited in capitalist patriarchy in order
to maintain the dominating relationships. Today, women are often exposed to
multiple types of burden within relationships of wage- and reproductive-labour.
Wage labourers exploit reproductive labourers within the framework of domestic
modes of production ─ which are still an aspect of the familial structures
of society ─ in order to have the physical and psychological abilities
to be exploited by capital. In accordance with Marxist feminism, here we can
also speak of a class relationship that is being constituted by the transfer
of unpaid labour from reproductive labourers to wage labourers and finally to
capital. “domestic labor is a form of socially necessary labor that expands
the goods and services available to the working class beyond what it would be
possible to purchase with wages. […] The relations of production, exchange,
and distribution place those who earn wages in a position to gain access to
the material conditions of reproduction and, consequently, in a position of
power over those with little or no access to those conditions. […] Sexual inequality
is one among the many forms of inequality thus generated by the mode of production
within the working class […] The contradictions between capital and labor, between
production and reproduction, and the protracted class struggle thereby generated
are the determinants of the contradictory nature of the relations between working-class
men and women” (Gimenez 1978: 77, 79, 80; see also Delphy 1975, Ehrenreich 1976,
Kuhn/Wolpe 1978).
So also in the area of reproductive labor, we
have a asymmetrical distribution and control of economic information, i.e. resources.
Reproductive labourers depend on money as the general resource and commodity
that must be earned by wage labour. Either they are wage labourers additionally
or/and they depend upon wage labour within familial structures. They are always
threatened by violence and the withdrawal of resources, e.g. also when women
can not hold out manifold types of burden. Reproductive labourers often have
less rights than wage labourers who are “free” in a double sense, they do not
have social security, collective agreements, unions fighting for them etc. Although
we are witnessing various forms of housewifization today (Mies 1984), wage labourers
are still in a relatively privileged situation in comparison to reproductive
and immigrant workers who are exposed to various types of super-exploitation.
So, super-exploitation also exists within the
framework of racist relationships of productions. These relationships are generally
very bad paid and immigrant workers only have minimal forms of social security
(this is also true for peripheral labour relationships such as part time work).
Racism is an ideology, wage labourers often participate in its social interspersion
in order to maintain their relative privileged situation. Labourers in racist
relationships of production only have minimal or no economic resources, political
rights and influence on the cultural formation of norms and values. They are
confronted with large exclusions concerning economical, political and cultural
information. The super-exploitation of immigrant workers constitutes a class
relationships, their precarious situation is maintained by capital and by wage
labourers who are taken in by racist ideologies (surely this is not true for
all wage labourers, but in many parts of the West for large parts of the working
class; e.g. in Austria, at the last general elections about 50% of the labourers
elected the right-wing-extremist and racist Freedom Party headed by Jörg Haider).
Class relationships always refer to the exclusive
control of resources, i.e. economical information, by groups which force others
to use these resources in order to accumulate further and new resources. In
the case of capitalism, these resources are commodities and capital. Exclusive
control also always means the use of violence or at least the threat of violence.
This shows that exclusive social information can only operate by making use
of repression. In capitalism, economical information is being exclusively controlled.
In bourgeois society, also political information
is exclusive social information. Representative democracy only has a very low
degree of social self-organisation because decisions are not made by those who
are effected by the resulting political information. Today, laws are the dominating
types of political information. They are characteristic for societies that depend
on the principle of domination. Elections are a type of competition and result
in dichotomies of government/opposition and parliament/people. This means the
constitution of exclusiveness and the delegation of the competence of reaching
decisions to an oligarchic group. The representative model does not advance
social self organisation, it depends on the exclusive control of political and
economical information.
In the representative political system we are
confronted with asymmetries and dichotomies in a double sense. First, the dichotomy
of electorate and the ones elected. Secondly, the dichotomies of government/opposition
and majority/minority. Hence this political system can not be seen as being
socially self-organised. It has been developing in parallel to bourgeois society
and in accordance to the principle of exclusivity. Exclusion and competition
are basic principles in bourgeois economics and politics.
The
state enforces and reinforces the exclusive control of social information. The
state is always a bourgeois state and fulfils several functions in the total
existing system of domination: 1. Organisation of the infrastructure of capital
accumulation, capitalist production and reproduction: research and development,
science, education, health, transport, law, preservation of the labourers as
object of exploitation, subsidies, aspects of finance and credit, taxation,
urban renewal, town planning, conservation, regional planning etc. The state
is the planner of capitalist society. Capital is not able to control and plan
social conflicts and class struggle alone, it needs state mediation. The state
is necessarily a nation state, because national control enables easier access
to markets for capital and labour power. The reproduction of the existing relationships
can be easier controlled on a national scale. 2. Repressive guarding of the
capital-relationship by law, police, military, secret service and the state
monopoly on violence. The state is necessary for the violent and repressive
suppression of exploited classes that could attack the fundamentals of this
situation. The existence of the state means the centralisation of the social
potential for violence in an entity that has been made independent from the
process of reproduction. This state entity has some degree of autonomy and is
not immediately tied to the economic development. For capital, the state is
the instrument for the enforcement of its interest and also the organiser of
the outer framework of the realisation of such interests. 3. Organisation of
counter-tendencies in case of social crises and falling profit rates which are
due to the social antagonisms of capitalism. When the mechanisms of the self-reproduction
of capitalism fail, regulative instances such as the state or private initiatives
try to re-establish a stabile phase of accumulation 4. organisation of the unity of the various
fractions of capital (see Poulantzas 1978). Classes are no homogenous units,
they are internally fragmented. The state is a factor of cohesion, it holds
the capitalist formation of society together. The state organises the block
of power, i.e. the dominating classes and their fractions, and formulates general
capitalist interests that unite the fragmented and competing fractions of capital.
5. pacification of the exploited: in order to avoid the maintenance of the capitalist
order by making use of direct force, the state acts as a mass-integrative apparatus.
Here, the regulation of the class relationships by instruments such as social
partnerships, concessions to the organisations of the working class, the unions
and the class-neutral appearance of the state are important. The latter refers
to the fact that the state pretends to stand for the realisation of labour interests
in order to avoid the appearance of the essence of the class character of the
state. The state tries to produce a consent between dominators and the dominated,
hence it always includes aspects of hegemony: “the State is the entire complex
of practical and theoretical activities with which the ruling class not only
justifies and maintains its dominance, but manages to win the active consent
of those over whom it rules“ (Gramsci 1971: 244).
The
internal organisation of the state functions in accordance with the principle
of exclusivity, the political information/laws that are produced are a type
of exclusive social information. And the state is a necessary entity of bourgeois
society that organises various conditions of the exclusive formation of economical,
political and cultural information in capitalism. The state is neither independent
from, nor determined by the capitalist economy. Rather, it has a relative autonomy,
i.e. there are also interests in the political and state structure of the existing
society that are formed independent from economical interests and relate to
the asymmetrical control of political power. But there are also interests and
decisions in the structure of the state that are enforced by the state and that
are necessary in order to establish exclusive economical information, i.e. private
property, commodity production and the accumulation of capital. So state-political
information also relates to economical information and certain aspects of it
are being influenced by economic processes and interests. Political information
constituted by the state also transforms economical information and it always
has an exclusive character and means the carrying out of relationships of domination.
In Fuchs
(2001), I argued that existing political models that stress elements of direct
democracy ─ such as the political system of Switzerland ─ are confronted
with various types of exclusion (e.g. the dichotomies of majority/minority,
dominators/dominated). Plebiscitary elements have also been used in the political
systems of fascist states: There are majority-based decisions on regulative
issues, but the questions that are being decided are formulated by the regime.
Plebiscites have been used in order to legitimate fascist systems by arguing
that these regimes have a democratic character. Such arguments hold that all
decisions are made by the people. But in reality, fascism relies on a charismatic
type of domination. The will of the people is highly manipulated by hegemonic
processes and mechanisms. This leads to an identity of the subjective interests
of the masses and the leader, the people trusts its leader and hence decides
in the way the fascist elite plans it. Additionally, representatives of the
objective interests of minorities, the exploited and the working class are repressed
violently or killed. Fascist plebiscites do not at all have something in common
with democracy, self-organisation and inclusive social information. In fact,
power is centralised and totally carried out in top-down-processes. Such social
information is a totally exclusive one, there is no degree of self-organisation.
Fascist plebiscites negate the true meaning of direct democracy, they do not
advance participation.
Capitalist culture as the way norms and values
are being constituted today, is heavily influenced by the mass media. With the
transition to information-societal capitalism, these media are even becoming
yet more influential by making use of modern information and communication technologies
(ICT). These technologies have a dialectical character: They can be used in
a way that reinforces existing relationships of domination, but also in a liberating
manner. On the one hand, mass culture leads to the forestalment of social change
and to stream-lined, one-dimensional mass-individuals. Hence freedom only means
freedom to consume, the “free” selection from a diversified spectrum of commodities.
All of this results in the manipulation of thinking, consciousness and actions,
one-dimensionality appears (Marcuse 1964, Horkheimer 1946, Adorno/Horkheimer
1969), oppositional movements and goals are forestalled to a certain degree.
The cultural channels and mediums are being controlled exclusively, the transmitted
contents are influenced and produced by information-monopolies. So, also cultural
information today is a type of exclusive social information. Monopolies heavily
influence the general constitution of norms and values, whereas the scattered
individuals are objects of ideologies and propaganda. They can hardly influence
the formation of cultural information and the constitution of political information.
Typically for capitalism today is the cyber-media-business-complex which changes
the public in such a way that scandals – which are often presented in extremely
sexualised and racist forms – are becoming the main contents of reporting. The
result is further standardisation of consciousness, manipulation, helplessness
and powerlessness.
Herbert
Marcuse (1964) stresses in this context that the cultural industry presents
contents that seem to be wild, obscene and unmoral – and hence they are harmless.
Categories like wage labour and commodity-consumption are presented by the mass
media as something obvious, but this is a type of totalitarian obviousness that
naturalises social compulsions. Marcuse says that the individuals introject
the speech and language of the ruling classes, they have false consciousness
and false needs. Max Horkheimer (1946) stresses that all of this leads to the
production of instrumental reason: Reactions are traced out exactly, no additional
effort is necessary, actions seem to be automated and are no longer questioned.
Marcuse
(1937b) argues that individuals do not necessary have false consciousness, they
can also develop critical thinking and actions. Today culture for Marcuse is
coined by domination and it manipulates, hence it is affirmative culture. People
feel happy, although they are not. Manifestations of culture could also have
anticipating effects, they can inspire fantasy and hence act as anticipations
of a better, free world. On the one hand, certain cultural manifestations stabilise
the existing order, on the other hand certain manifestations also convey the
picture of a order that is better than the existing one.
Considering
the new ICT, this view of Marcuse is very important: Concerning the application
of these media in the course of social struggle, the situation is an ambivalent
one. On the one hand there is the technologically mediated production and simulation
of hyper-reality that generates new meanings by putting together different,
de-contextualized symbols in order to steer public opinion in a certain manner.
In this context, the thesis of cultural industry formulated by Marcuse, Adorno
and Horkheimer is right. It says that the cultural industry produces false consciousness
and needs, one-dimensional mass-individuals (Marcuse 1964) and instrumental
reason (Horkheimer 1946). The new technologies are exactly applied in this manner.
But on the other hand, there is the possibility for protest movements to make
use of ICT in order to reinforce the effects they have on society (see Fuchs
2001). The new technologies reflect existing relationships of domination, but
nonetheless their adoption in a productive manner by protest movements is possible.
Protest in the real world can be supported by a virtual culture of protest and
a technologically mediated optimisation of manners and structures of political
self-organisation.
Political and economical relationships have their
own types of culture, culture is only possible in relationship with politics
and economics, although it has a certain degree of relative autonomy. In the
framework of the complex interplay of culture and politics, hegemony - as a phenomenon that is typical for
societies that are based on the principle of domination - is constituted. Hegemony can be seen
in accordance with Antonio Gramsci as “the ‘spontaneous’ consent of the masses
who must ‘live’ those directives [of the state, CF], modifying their own habits,
their own will, their own convictions to conform with those directives and with
the objectives which they propose to achieve“ (Gramsci 1971: 266).
Gramsci stressed that the state strives to win
the consent of the ones who are dominated to this process (ibid., p. 244). In
this process of enforcing a consent between dominators and the dominated state-institutions
such as schools and law are important, but also private institutions - which are part of the cultural system
- are necessary. “The school as a positive
educative function, and the courts as a repressive and negative educative function,
are the most important state activities in this sense: but, in reality, a multitude
of other so-called private initiatives and activities tend to the same end -
initiatives and activities which form the apparatus of the political and cultural
hegemony of the ruling classes. [...] The state does have and request consent,
but it also ‘educates’ this consent, by means of the political and syndical
associations; these, however are private organisms, left to the private initiative
of the ruling class“ (Gramsci 1971: 258f). Hegemony always has political and
cultural aspects, it is formed in the framework of the complex relationships
between politics and culture.
Capitalist
culture is affirmative culture and hence we find an exclusive control of the
formation of norms and values. Cultural industry as a method of manipulation
produces needs and consciousness in certain forms. The formation of cultural
information today is mainly an exclusive process. But modern media can also
be used in oppositional manners. Here
we again find asymmetries and limitations, because these technologies are mainly
locations for capital accumulation and commodification. Nonetheless, modern
media can be used as a means of producing critical and oppositional information.
The
capitalist society we live in depends on exclusive social information in the
areas of economy, politics and culture. So it can be said that it has a very
low degree of social self-organisation. The exclusive character of social information
is related to the general antagonisms of capitalism. The essential antagonistic
structures of capitalism appear as exclusive economical, political and cultural
information. There are political-economical antagonisms such as class antagonisms;
an economic antagonism between wealth and poverty, one between necessary and
surplus labour, one between use and exchange value, one between concrete and
abstract labour, one between productive forces and relations of production,
one between living and dead labour, one between the profit-based production
in single corporations and the total social demand, one between production and
consumption, one between the social character of production and the individual
appropriation of commodities and one between the producers and the means of
production (technology as an end in itself); political antagonisms such as the
fractioning of classes, global conflicts caused by the capitalist world system;
a cultural antagonisms that holds that it is not possible for all societies
to live in global peace and wealth because there are disproportional distributions
of global wealth and global relationships of domination/exploitation; and finally
an ecological antagonism: the ecology is being destroyed by the non-sustainable
mode of production advanced by capitalism, which needs the appropriation of
intact ecological resources in order to guarantee its own reproduction.
By
relating to the manipulative production of false consciousness and false needs
as a totalitarian aspect of the bourgeois system, Marcuse is referring to aspects
of hegemony. Hegemony as a characteristic of capitalist society shows that large
parts of society are excluded from the processes of constituting social norms,
values and decisions. The discussion of the degree of inclusiveness and exclusiveness
of capitalist society which has shown that capitalism is based on exclusion
in all areas of society points out that Marcuse’s assessment that bourgeois
society is a pseudo-democracy and a totalitarian system is still true. But of
course there is also the question of which alternatives are possible. Marcuse
gave us some important hints on this topic which are quite useful in order to
interpret the concept of democracy in a liberating sense.
Marcuse
says that if democracy means self-government of free individuals and justice
for all, the realisation of democracy presupposes the abolishment of the existing
pseudo-democracy (Marcuse 1969: 296). A new society should be based on councils
which are organisations of self-determination in local assemblies (Marcuse 1972:
50). An immediate democracy would mean the effective, bottom-up control of power
(ibid.: 51). A direct democracy of the majority would be the right political
structure for the initial stages of socialism (ibid.: 58). Liberty would have
to diffuse into all social areas. Economic liberty would mean liberty from the
economy, and its current determination of the individuals. Political liberty
would mean the liberation of the individuals from a political systems that can
not be controlled by them. And mental liberty would mean the restoration of
individual thinking that has been absorbed by mass communication and indoctrination
(Marcuse 1961: 58).
The self-management
of corporations, plants and residental quarters would at first mean
unpolitical approaches, but they could pose the possibilities to spread unconventional
information and the development of core-structures of local organisation. By
further developments a political character could emerge (Marcuse 1973/74: 168).
At some points of Marcuses’s works, it seems like he is in favour of a state-“dictatorship
of the proletariat” which is part of a transitional phase on the way to a free
society (see e.g. 1965c: 149f; 139: 146, 1947: thesis 16), whereas in other
writings he is in favour of the anarchistic thesis that an immediate transition
into the real of freedom is possible (due to the level the material conditions
have reached and other factors). Marcuse says that the strategy of the New Left
is a concept of socialism that includes the break with the continuum of dependence
– from the beginning (Marcuse 1972: 14). He also expresses his view that
state socialism did not change the existing apparatus of production and social
needs fundamentally. It sustained the fundamentals of class society – the abolishment
of the classes; the transition into a free society would presuppose those changes
that state socialism aimed at (Marcuse 1947: 137).
Whereas
theses no. 16 and 19 of Marcuse’s “33 Theses” (1947) speak in favour of a dictatorship
of the proletarians, such a view is negated by the theses no. 18, 21, 22, 23,
24, 25, 26, 29. The latter support the anarchistic thesis. Marcuse says that
the two-phase-model which distinguishes between socialism and communism is very
dangerous because this could strengthen the view that socialism is only an enhanced
type of capitalism. He says that an imitation and surpassing of capitalism is
only possible by neglecting the abolishment of domination. But this would make
socialism meaningless. The first phase would breed a mentality of subordination
and accommodation that renders the transition to the second phase very improbable.
It seems like Marcuse was in favour of some aspects of anarchism for some time.
He said e.g. that the construction of socialism is not an arising from capitalism,
but a fundamental difference to capitalism. The socialist society is the negation
of the capitalist world. He sees neither nationalisation of the means of production
nor a higher standard of living as such a negation. But the abolishment of domination,
exploitation and labor would constitute such a negating force. The socialisation
of the means of production, their management by the immediate producers would
be the presupposition for socialism. Where this characteristic can not be found,
there is no socialism. Marcuse argues that the state-bureaucratic control of
the means of production does not abolish wage labor. This would only be possible
by an immediate self-management of the producers, i.e. if they can decide, what,
how much and how long they produce. Such an anarchy and disintegration would
probably be the only way to break up the capitalist reproduction and to generate
an interregnum or vacuum in which a change of needs and the generation of freedom
can take place. Anarchy would announce the abolishment of domination and disintegration
would remove the power of the apparatus of production over the individuals.
This would at least mean the greatest possibilities for the negation of class
society (Marcuse 1947: theses 24, 25, 26). The apparatuses of state and production,
Marcuse says, can not simply be overtaken because concerning their whole structure
they are apparatuses of suppression (thesis 29).
Marcuse’s
view of socialism as a democratisation of all areas of life that negates capitalism
as well as state-socialism anticipated later discussions about an integrative
democracy. I want to tear this topic slightly by mentioning a few aspects of
the thinking of Murray Bookchin and Cornelius Castoriadis. Murray Bookchin stresses
the need for “municipalization
of the economy – and its management by the community as part of a politics of
self-management” (Bookchin 1992) and he calls for
“community self-management based on a fully participatory democracy – in in
the highest form of direct action, the full empowerment of the people in determining
the destiny of society” (Bookchin 1989). He describes the democratic self-management
of a qualitative new society as communalism (Bookchin 1990, 1992, 1994). “Democracy
generically defined, then, is the direct management of society in face-to-face
assemblies — in which policy is formulated by the resident citizenry
and administration is executed by mandated and delegated councils. […]
I wish to propose that the democratic and potentially practicable dimension
of the libertarian goal be expressed as Communalism […] A Communalist
democracy would oblige us to develop a public sphere — and in the Athenian meaning
of the term, a politics — that grows in tension and ultimately in a decisive
conflict with the state. Confederal, antihierarchical and collectivist, based
on the municipal management of the means of life rather than their control by
vested interests (such as workers' control, private control and, more dangerously,
state control), it may justly be regarded as the processual actualization of
the libertarian ideal as a daily praxis” (Bookchin 1994).
Cornelius
Castoriadis (1955, 1980, 1990, 1993) conceived the term “autonomous society”
for a society without domination, exploitation and hierarchy. Although he used
the term socialism in earlier works for describing the “masses
conscious and perpetual self-managerial activity” (Castoriadis 1955), he later
said that he no longer wants to use the terms socialism and communism (Castoriadis
1980), and so he conceived the term autonomous society. Autonomous
society includes autonomouse individuals – and vice versa (Castoriadis 1980).
For Castoriadis it is all about real social freedom and a maximum of individual possibilities
for action that can be guaranteed by the institutions of society. A free society
would mean execution of power by a community in which all people can participate
in the same manner (ibid.). For Castoriadis equality means an equal distribution
of power, i.e. equal and egalitarian possibilities to participate in society
that we do not find in capitalist society. His goal was the sublation of heteronomy,
the end of the domination of society by certain institutions and groups and
the emergence of a new, self-institutioning society (ibid.). Result would be
a collective self-management of all areas of society. For Castoriadis, self-management
and self-organisation mean the self-institutioning of society. He speaks of
the self-organisation of machines, tools, means of labour, conditions of work
and life, education, housing and so on. The concept of self-organisation is
not just used in an economic sense by Castoriadis, he applies it as an integrative
and extensive concept that applies to the whole of society and all its constituting
areas (ibid.). Castoriadis (1993) stresses that a self-managed society is one
in which all decisions are reached by the social totality of those who are effected
by the subject of decision. This is a co-operative process. Castoriadis’ concept
of autonomous society is a very good example for a liberatrian democracy and
that such an understanding of democracy includes social self-organisation of
all areas of society.
Due
to the totalitarian character of capitalism and its pseudo-democracy such alternative
lines of discussion are very important. Just as his concepts of technology and
culture, Marcuse’s concept of democracy is also a dialectical one (Negt 1999).
It is not all about a “sublation of democracy”, democracy is not seen vulgarly
as synonymous with representation, it is about real democracy as the immediate
self-management of all areas of life and representative democracy as a false
type of democracy. These are two types of democracy for Marcuse – the liberating
and the bourgeois one. His goal was the sublation of bourgeois democracy and
the establishment of a truly democratic society.
As
already mentioned, Marcuse clearly distinguished between bourgeois democracy
and fascism. If there is only the alternative between one of the two, he clearly
was in favour of bourgeois democracy. In his American exile, Marcuse analysed
German fascism. Many aspects of this analysis are still important today. Marcuse
(1941b, 1942) characterises the new German mentality that emerged in National-Socialism
and can be characterised by unlimited politicisation, unlimited disillusionment
(everything that can not be supported by clear facts is seen as fraud and deception),
cynical matter-of-factness (the Germans are brutal pragmatics who judge everything,
including fascism, only from the view of their own direct material advantages),
new heathenism (anti-Semitism, terrorism, social Darwinism, anti-intellectualism,
naturalism as expressions against Christian morals; nature is seen as the source
of all impulses, urges, inclinations and wishes), shift of taboos (sexual, familiar,
moral ones; abolishment of sexual taboos) and a bond between the masses and
the regime (the Germans see the destruction of the Hitler-regime as their personal
destruction). Marcuse argued that this new mentality would not automatically
vanish with National-Socialism.
NS
postulated the destruction of the family, of bourgeois marriage and an attack
on patriarchal norms. It appealed to a constructed “nature” of humans, put national-racist
ties (the Volksgemeinschaft) against patriarchal authority, body against
intellect, soul against mechanisation, open air and nature against the bourgeois
home. NS negated the difference between state and society, society and the individual,
labor and spare time. All was integrated into a new whole, the Volksgemeinschaft,
everything had to function in accordance with it.
Marcuse
says that the language of NS simplifies complex structures of sentences, it
transforms personal relationships into impersonal things and events and it centers
around irrational ideas like people, race, blood, soil and Reich. People (Volk)
and race as well as birth determined by origin and location are treated as facts.
One no longer talks about society, but instead about the national identity of
a people (Volk), about race instead of class, blood and soil (Blut
und Boden) instead of property rights. Marcuse further says that the majority
of all Germans has accepted this language and identifies itself with the Nazi-regime.
He
argued that the typical characteristics of the one dimensional-man could already
be found in German fascism. The individuals would act with great personal initiative,
spontaneity and personality, but their thinking, feelings and actions would
be determined by the technological rationality of National-Socialism. Language
and thinking of National-Socialism, Marcuse says, have been introjected into
the individuals’ characters. The authoritarian personality of people in the
nazi-system as a mass base of fascism would also have to do with the transformation
of the industrial society into an authoritarian society. Marcuse (1941b) argues
that NS deprives the people of their individuality and only leaves their bestial
self-interests and egoism. Hence they would be very susceptible to standardisation
from above.
In
the 1970ies, Marcuse again and again warned that the danger of fascism is not
banned, he feared a transition into a neo-fascist society in the USA. The authoritarian
personality and the one-dimensional man are not only the mass base of fascism,
they are also characteristic of late capitalism. This also shows that the danger
of fascism has not vanished. The end of National-Socialism has not brought an
end to the mentality that has been connected with this system. On the contrary,
this mentality still exists in specific post-fascist types in the core regions
of former German fascism (and in other countries as well). One-dimensional man
and authoritarian personality have become functional elements of capitalism;
the latter makes use of them in order to carry itself into the individuals’
consciousness and to produce and introject false needs and false consciousness.
This continuation resp. this new creation is so dangerous, frightening and unfortunately
still topical, hence the danger of fascism still exists.
The
social restructuring from Fordism to Postfordism and the neo-liberal politics
that accompany it have lead to an increase of the global problems and an intensification
and enlargement of the precarious conditions large parts of the world population
have to live in. It is no surprise that the one-dimensional and authoritarian
mass base of fascism that still exists increasingly falls on fertile political
soil. This results in a boom of right-wing-extremist and neo-fascist groups
and parties. In the core regions of former German fascism the authoritarian
personality mixes with post-fascist relationships and produces explosive conditions
that are very dangerous.
By
analysing the language and thinking of neo-fascist demagogues and their authoritarian
mass base, one sees that most of the characteristics that Marcuse mentioned
are still important. E.g. the cynical matter-of-factness, large parts of the
people consider everything only by the immediate material advantages they can
derive from it. This results in a massive support for racist ideologies because
in one-dimensional thinking the worsening of the material situation of others
results automatically in the hope for the improvement of one’s own poor existence.
Cynical matter-of-factness is a characteristic of the authoritarian personality
as a mass base of neo-fascism and a strategy of propaganda deliberately applied
by demagogues. Unlimited disillusionment results in an absolute objectification
of authoritarian ideologies today: Certain arguments that are employed by racist
and neo-fascist ideologies are presented as rational and unquestionable facts
although they are really irrational and aim directly at the prevailing aggressive
structures of desire, at emotionality and subliminal fears. As already at the
time of German fascism, what we find is a rationalisation of the irrational
that closes people’s minds fully against rational counter-arguments, even if
they make use of statistics and numerical data. Nature is often substituted
by culture in neo-fascist ideologies, a bonding between neo-fascist demagogues
and their mass base takes place; each argument that is employed against neo-fascism
and its political executors is regarded as being directed against their personal
existence by the individuals who support such views and ideologies. Demagogues
still try to appeal to the masses and their national identities which in reality
are nothing else than mere artificial constructions. The mass base recognises
itself in neo-fascist ideologies and its demagogues, it regards itself as identical
with the political demagogues and neo-fascist parties.
The
one-dimensional language of National-Socialism has been generalised after the
end of the Second World War by the rise and monopolisation of the mass media.
The yellow press and mass media make us of the personalisation of the objectified
and the objectification of social phenomena, they simplify complex facts and
cultivate a non-dialectical, primitive language that directly appeals to the
cynical matter-of-factness. This prevailing language of the mass media is also
the language of neo-fascism and its authoritarian mass base.
Marcuse’s
warnings of a new fascism and his characterisation of the fascist mentality
are still very important. The danger of fascism has not yet vanished, there
could still be situations where we have the alternative between the defence
of existing bourgeois democracy (which becomes more and more authoritarian)
and the rise of fascism. And still only Marcuse’s position would be the only
justifiable and good one.
Advanced
culture, Marcuse says, encompasses elements of opposition against the existing
totality. This would be part of the Great Refusal – the protest against that
which is (Marcuse 1964: 63). Existing society tries to get rid of these elements.
Means of mass communication accelerate the transformation of culture into commodities.
Hence, only sales and exchange values of culture are important today. The popularisation
of advanced culture forestalls oppositional and critical elements by submitting
culture to the laws of the market.
Marcuse
is not against the massive diffusion of culture into society by channels such as TV, cinema
or radio, but he stresses that this “cultural machine” fulfils certain ideological
functions in capitalism: “It is good that almost everyone can now have the fine
arts at his fingertips, by just turning a knob on his set, or by just stepping
into his drugstore. In this diffusion, however, they become cogs in a culture-machine
which remakes their content” (Marcuse 1964: 65).
Marcuse
says that culture means the whole of life in society, the unity of on the one
hand the areas of idealistic reproduction (culture in narrower sense, the mental
world) and on the other also the areas of material reproduction (“civilisation”)
(Marcuse 1937b: 62). He (1965a) stresses that specific views, beliefs, traditions,
acquisitions etc. are important elements of culture and that culture is the
complex of moral, intellectual and aesthetic goals (values) that are regarded
as the purpose of organising, dividing and controlling labor (1965a: 115).
Marcuse
makes a distinction between civilisation and culture (the latter in a narrower
sense). The first refers to the realm of necessity, social necessary labor and
actions where man can not be himself. Culture refers to a higher dimension of
human fulfilment and autonomy, it wants to end the struggle for existence. Marcuse
characterises civilisation by material labor, the working day, the realm of
necessity, nature and operational thinking; culture as an antagonism to civilisation
by mental work, holiday, free time, the realm of freedom, mind and non-operational
thinking. He says that in the advanced industrial society, culture is incorporated
into labor. With such an integration of culture into society, society tends
to become totalitarian even in those areas where democratic forms and institutions
have still existed (Marcuse 1965a: 117). Traditionally culture has had transcendental
goals that anticipated the realm of freedom. But technological civilisation
tends to destroy these goals of culture. This results in an assimilation of
labor and relaxation, failing and enjoyment, art and household, psychology and
management. So culture becomes affirmative. A necessary space for the development
of autonomy and opposition is locked by society.
Concerning Marcuse’s works on art and culture,
some of his late writings such as „Counter-Revolution and Revolt“ (1972) and
„The Permanence of Art“ (1977) are very important. He says that something characteristic
of art is its aesthetic form. This refers all qualities (like meaning, rhythm
or contrast) that form a closed whole of an opus. Aesthetics, Marcuse says,
result in a separation of art from reality and in a distance between both. The
aesthetic universe contradicts reality. Art is a part of mental culture, hence
it contradicts civilisation. Marcuse says that art reveals another dimension
of the existing reality: the one of possible liberation (Marcuse 1972: 88f).
He argues that the radical qualities of art, especially of literature, are liberation
and the accusations against the existing totality. But this could only be the
place where art transcends existing reality (Marcuse 1977: 201). The aesthetic
dimension of art is autonomous from material labor, it is separated from the
material process of production. Of course, art is also a commodity, but this
fact, Marcuse argues, does not change its substance – truth. The beautiful as
part of the aesthetic dimension of art negates the world of commodities. Marcuse
says that he finds it hard to realise a specific class character of art and
to derive such a character from arts existence as a commodity. Of course, art
would be something elitist in elitist, bourgeois society, it is only accessible
for a privileged minority; this means a class character of art in certain respects,
but for Marcuse the distance of art from reality also is constitutive for its
aspects of liberation. He says that in a free society, art would no longer be
elitist, but it would still be distanced from real life.
Marcuse
does not want to distinguish between “bourgeois” and “proletarian” art/culture.
He says that the critical, negating, transcending qualities of art are objectified
in its aesthetic dimension, not in its contents. In a society where the proletarians
are not revolutionary, there could be no revolutionary-proletarian art. It would
be a problem for various Marxist theories of art that the proletariat does not
negate existing society, that it is in fact integrated into the social totality.
Hence such theories, Marcuse argues, should no longer speak of a specific proletarian
art and they should stop looking for the revolutionary contents of art. Art
is always distanced from revolutionary practice, it can not represent revolution.
Art and culture are only united by their engagement for revolution. Art can
not be part of revolutionary practice because in doing so it would have to become
concrete, it would have to act in relationship to the existing life. But this
would result in a destruction of its aesthetic dimension, this would mean the
end of art. Marcuse e.g. does not consider literature revolutionary if it is
written for the proletarians or for a revolution. Revolutionary art could only
refer to the opus itself where the aesthetic dimension is the content itself
(Marcuse 1977: 197). If art shakes ones experiences and conveys the picture
of another reality, it has subversive qualities.
Rock-music,
guerilla-theater or poetry of the free press, Marcuse says, are not anti-art
due to their life-likeness, they are a one-dimensional part of the existing
order for him because they destroy the distance of art from real life (Marcuse
1972: 101). He further argues that with rock-music, music becomes a collective
happening. The repeating gestures, the turning and shaking of the bodies which
only touch each other very rarely (if they do at all) – this all would seem
like remaining on the same spot all the time, like a mass meeting that scatters
itself soon. Marcuse says that this type of music is an imitation, a mimesis
of real aggression (Marcuse 1972: 112f). On the other hand Marcuse seems to
be impressed by the folk-rock-songs of Bob Dylan. He says that what is decisive
here is that the political dimension remains obliged to the aesthetic one (Marcuse 1972: 114f). Art and revolution
would be connected in the aesthetic dimension. Art answers to the total character
of repression and alienation with alienation (Marcuse says that some examples
for this are the music of John Cage, Karl Heinz Stockhausen and Pierre Boulez).
In
the Cultural Studies and in the discourses and discussions that have resulted
from it, much has been said about the possibilities of subversion in and by
music. I do not generally believe that music automatically becomes one-dimensional,
de-personalising and stupefactious by becoming popular. The degree of one-dimensionality
of music is relative autonomous from its degree of dissemination. If this would
not be the case, it would mean that Independent Music which has emerged in various
sub cultures in the 80ies has automatically had subversive characteristics.
By the heavy commercialisation of this genre in the 1990ies one would have to
conclude that this assumed subversive character of alternative rock-music has
come to a full end. I do not want to argue in such ways because such assumptions
seem to be a little bit short-sighted.
Various
vulgar arguments hold that rock- and pop-music (these two categories can not
be separated) can never be liberating in any sense due to their existence as
commodities. Of course each type, genre, oeuvre, opus and piece of music is
a commodity, that is a very obvious fact, but I would agree with Herbert Marcuse
that one can not derive an affirmative or liberating character of music from
its commodity-form. What is essential, is the substance of music, elements of
cultural manifestations that lie beneath the surface and aim at human experiences
and imagination. Pop and rock are bulk goods and parts of mass culture, but
they are due to this fact neither automatically liberating, not automatically
affirming the existing totality. They are not less elitist than other cultural
manifestations because its recipients are also limited to certain groups and
life-styles. Pop is not democratic because culture and art are as a whole part
of an unfree, undemocratic world. But nonetheless culture can stimulate imagination
and go beyond the existing totality.
Due
to my own aesthetic world of experiences, I think that Marcuse’s argument that
the aesthetic dimension of rock-music is opposed to the beautiful and the liberating
effects of imagination is rather amusing. I believe that neither the aesthetic
dimension, nor the content of cultural manifestations automatically has an affirmative
or a liberating character. I would also not reduce the liberating dimension
to the aesthetic one. Various youth- and left sub-cultures are nowadays looking
for a specific revolutionary content of cultural manifestations, especially
of music. But the picking up of specific aspects of left politics and views
into musical contents does not automatically result in liberating types of culture.
On the contrary, also the absence of such contents does not automatically result
in affirmative types of culture. Large parts of punk- and hardcore-music thematically
address classical leftist topics – anti-fascism, anti-racism, anti-racism, anti-capitalism.
At the same time they reproduce the existing one-dimensional universe of language
and consciousness in their aesthetic dimension and contents. I am referring
to the simplicity and monotony of the song structures, missing
abstraction, the permanent repetition of simple musical basic structures,
the reduction of complex relationships to simple paroles and formulas in regards
to contents and language. Musical form and content are becoming identical with
reality, the non-identity of liberating cultural manifestations ceases to exist,
the content is identical with ideological propaganda as put forward by the mass
media, the rainbow press and politics, the aesthetic dimension is identical
with the lack of abstraction of uniform, monotonous, mechanical movements and
activities in production. Cultures becomes entangled with civilisation.
A
different and even opposing example is the music of the Goldenen Zitronen. Aesthetic
dimension as well as content are much more complex and take on broken forms,
the content abstracts itself in its apparent absurdity and its alienation from
reality and ordinary language, but on the other hand it also refers critically
to this universe of false words and beliefs. One-dimensional scraps of words
are disembedded from their contexts, arranged in new forms and transferred to
other contexts. This results in the transcendence of the bad and false reality
(regarding content), and in references to this existing universe. The aesthetic
dimension is essentially abstract, sometimes it seems like improvisation. It
is not beautiful in a classical sense, but that should not be considered as
a presupposition for the liberating character of music. On the other hand, also
an atonality of music does not automatically result in a liberating character.
The music the Goldenen Zitronen produce nowadays can not be consumed easily,
you have to exert your mind and imagination, concentration on aesthetics and
content is needed. And hence both of these elements form a complex unity that
stimulates imagination and goes beyond the realm of necessity.
Neither
each form, nor each content of cultural manifestations results in transcending
imaginations that go beyond the existing totalitarian society. Popular culture
is musically dominated by primitive types of disco- and techno-music which are
important parts of the existing one-dimensional universe. This does neither
automatically result from the fact that they are commodities just like all types
of culture, nor from the fact that it is a mass product of consumption. It results
from the one-dimensionality of its form and content. The content – if it exists
– imitates the existing world and its language. The form is characterised by
monotony and repetition of similar patterns that remind us of our miserable
lives in capitalism and wage labour. The repetitive, hypnotic monotony of the
music reflects the one of social existence and consciousness. Such cultural
manifestations indeed transform – just like Marcuse said – culture into civilisation,
they are affirmative types of culture that forestall all transcending imagination.
On
the contrary we find various types of modern electronic music and of so-called
post rock which strive towards an increase of their own complexity. E.g. the
electronic and solely instrumental musical landscapes created by Mouse on Mars
require attention and imagination, various levels of listening experience that
temporarily harmonise and temporarily work against each other can be found in
parallel. There are no unequivocal listening experiences for the recipients,
each time different results in experience can be reached. The deepening into
this music enables one to dive into other levels of experience that simulate
fantasy and imagination. What shows up is freedom in a world of misery, slavery
and exploitation. By transcending the existing totality, the future is anticipated.
Mouse on Mars say and effect much more without words than all different types
of one-dimensional music that rely on phrases and false language together. Post
rock in its various types as represented by e.g. Labradford, Mogwai, Magnog,
Godspeed You Black Emperor! or Tortoise relies on broken forms, surprises, the
unexpected, the oscillation between intensification and vanishing, a play with
silence and noise, the complexity of the forms. The form again requires concentration
and imagination, it goes beyond the one-dimensional reproduction of ever repeating
sounds, it stimulates imagination. The content in the sense of linguistic levels
often vanishes completely. Post rock negates one-dimensional language by oftenly
including phases without words. Everything seems to be said in postfordist capitalism,
the silence of the words expresses the disdain of bad and false reality. Quite
often post rock means phases of slowness, almost stand-still and vanishing (e.g.
Low, Savoy Grand, Codeine, Cat Power, Tindersticks or Arab Strap). The aesthetic
form negates social reality. People are confronted with global, ultra-fast flows
of information and capital today that deprive them of their individuality and
energy. Flexibility, adaptability, fast change and modernity are necessary
permanently – modernise or die. Leisure and labor are becoming identical,
culture is almost total civilisation, free time means fitting in, relaxation
becomes high-performance-sports. Post rock often is slow music, it puts a counterpoint
to the permanent compulsions for acceleration and speed that subsume humans
totally under capital.
In one-dimensional
society, musical contents are susceptible to regressive, reactionary and anti-emancipatory
elements. Schlager-music and nazi-rock are only two examples. But this does
not mean that music as such is affirmative or regressive, but false music is
a logical result of the false capitalist totality. Nonetheless form and content
can reach a liberating character although they are also always elements of the
totality of affirmative culture and elements of the containment of social change
by mere escape from the bad reality and by their existence as medium of the
regeneration of the physical and psychic abilities to work. I want to give you
one example for musical contents that stimulate liberating aspects of imagination.
The contents
of the songs of the band Blumfeld are lyrically structured and often refer to
left-wing political topics. The latter element does not automatically result
in a liberating musical character. What seems to be the important element to
me is that a dialectical language is employed that goes beyond the existing
one-dimensional universe of thinking and speaking. Blumfeld’s music needs mental
discourse, imagination and own interpretations in order to be understood. This
music makes sense and stimulates imagination by its contents, symbols, patterns,
structures and dialectical language. Commercials impose meanings and images
on commodities in order to sell them. What is wanted is not critical thinking
of potential consumers, but stupid, reflex-like reactions of the objects. Commercials
and mass culture make use of a manipulating language, they create new words
in order to praise commodities and to sell them. The language of the people
is essentially one-dimensional. A dialectical language on the contrary is a
negating one as suggested by Marcuse. Such a language seems to be present in
the musical lyrics of Blumfeld. The sentences negate predominating sentences,
contents name social antagonisms. Here music is related to real life, but nonetheless
its negating distance from the latter remains by its dialectic. Antagonisms
in ones own existence, antagonisms of life in the existing totality and the
state, antagonisms of love as a phenomenon that is coined by false society etc.
Imagination that can anticipate a qualitative different society can be felt
in form and content.
Some
last words on culture: What seems to be problematic is not the occupation with
art and culture and the search for liberation and politics of such manifestations.
Cultures covers the totality of all ways of life of society. It is a reflection
of concrete material relationships, but it unfolds own dimensions that can not
be reduced to the economy or politics. Hence taking issue with culture, its
aesthetic and its contents can throw light on the relationships of society.
The politicisement of art/culture, the art of emancipatory politics – both is
necessary. What is problematically is the reduction of political practice to
a cultural level because – as Marcuse pointed out – non-affirmative culture
is essentially alienated from political practice, it can present and anticipate
imaginative pictures of liberation, it can anticipate the realm of freedom,
stimulate imagination, emancipatory consciousness and needs can recognize themselves
in art. For all of that, various cultural manifestations are useful, good and
necessary – but they are no types of political practice. Emancipation is a social
process of real life, liberation is an essentially practical process, one of
social self-organisation. Post-modernist types of culturalism that objectify
social liberation into commodities and consumption and see liberation as a part
of the objectified dimension of commodities, are affirming existing society.
Marcuse says that art can not change the world, but it can contribute to a change
of consciousness and desires that can change the world (Marcuse 1977: 217).
In
this situation, Critical Theory, the works of Herbert Marcuse and their interpretation
in relation to topical events and changes are very necessary. Marcuse’s dialectical
categories of technology, democracy and culture also stress the liberating aspects
of these categories. We must abolish the affirmative aspects and organise liberating
technology, culture and democracy in the framework of a new society. It is all
about a qualitatively different society that includes another technology, another
culture, another democracy and another economy, i.e. about the excessive transformation
of all areas of life and society. In order to accomplish this we need active,
self-organising subjects whose consciousness and actions go beyond the existing
false totality. This is not something impossible. Neither unlimited optimism,
nor unlimited pessimism are advisable. What is decisive is the intervening power
of self-organisation as part of a great refusal. In order to accomplish this
a re-reading or first time-reading of Herbert Marcuse’s works can contribute
in sustainable ways.
Best,
Steven/Kellner, Douglas (1997) The Postmodern
Turn. New York/London. Guilford Press
Murray
Bookchin, Radical Politics in an Era of Advanced Capitalism, In: Green Perspectives, No. 18, Nov. 1989
Murray
Bookchin, Urbanization without Cities: The Rise and Decline of Citizenship
(Black Rose Press, 1992)
Murray
Bookchin, 1994, What is Communalism? The Democratic Dimension of Anarchism,
in Left Green Perspectives 31, http://www.leftgreen.org/issues/lgp31.html
Kurz, Robert (1991) Der Kollaps der Modernisierung. Frankfurt/Main.
Eichborn
[1] Another time Marx says e.g. that
technology is the „most powerful instrument for
shortening labour-time“ (Marx 1867, S. 430)
[2] For the difference between core-
and peripheral-workers see Atkinson (1984: 14ff) and Atkinson/Gregory (1986:
14).
[3] In Postfordism we do not only have
mass unemployment, but also precarious conditions of life for large parts
of the world population. This is not only true for the Third World (which
would be worse enough), there is also an increasing number of peripheral
spaces in the metropolis of the capitalist world system. Neo-conservatism
does not only result in the emergence of new job relationships, it also
results in a worsening of the social situation and the situation of wage
labor. It can be said that peripheral job relationships quite often have
a precarious character today (Möller 1990). There is nothing new about these
jobs, what we find is an old pattern: The betterment of the situation of
capital at the expense of wage labor.
[4] We consider means of production,
resources, decisions, social norms, laws, values and rules (the latter do
not need to be codified, they can also be established in the form of traditions
or habits) which are constituted during the course of social relationships
of several individuals as social information. In all social systems and
formations of society there are three manifestations of information: resources,
decisions and norms/values. They store information about past social actions
and simplify future social situations because by referring to social information
the basics of acting socially do not have to be formed in each such situation.
Social information can be seen as a durable foundation of social actions
which nonetheless changes dynamically.