2: The Closing of the Political Universe
The society
of total mobilization, which takes shape in the most advanced areas of industrial
civilization, combines in productive union the features of the Welfare State
and the Warfare State. Compared with its predecessors, it is in- deed a "new
society." Traditional trouble spots are being cleaned out or isolated,
disrupting elements taken in hand. The main trends are familiar: concentration
of the national economy on the needs of the big corporations, with the government
as a stimulating, supporting, and sometimes even controlling force; hitching
of this economy to a world-wide system of military alliances, monetary arrangements,
technical assistance and development schemes; gradual assimilation of blue-collar
and white-collar population, of leadership types in business and labor, of
leisure activities and aspirations in different social classes; fostering
of a pre-established harmony between scholarship and the national purpose;
invasion of the private household by the togetherness of public opinion; opening
of the bedroom to the media of mass communication.
In the political
sphere, this trend manifests itself in a marked unification or convergence
of opposites. Bipartisan- ship in foreign policy overrides competitive group
interests under the threat of international communism, and spreads to domestic
policy, where the programs of the big parties become ever more undistinguishable,
even in the degree of hypocrisy and in the odor of the cliches. This unification
of opposites bears upon the very possibilities of social change where it embraces
those strata on whose back the system progresses-that is, the very classes
whose existence once embodied the opposition to the system as a whole.
In the United States, one
notices the collusion and alliance between business and organized labor; in
Labor Looks
19
at
Labor: A Conversation, published by the Center
for the Study of Democratic Institutions in 1963, we are told that: 'What
has happened is that the union has become almost indistinguishable in its
own eyes from the corporation. We see the phenomenon today of unions and
corporations faintly lobbying. The union is not going to be able to
convince missile workers that the company they work for is a fink outfit when
both the union and the corporation are out lobbying for bigger missile contracts
and trying to get other defense industries into the area, or when they jointly
appear before Congress and jointly ask that missiles instead of bombers should
be built or bombs instead of missiles, depending on what contract they happen
to hold.’
The British
Labor Party, whose leaders compete with their Conservative
counterparts in advancing national interests, is hard put to save even a modest
program of partial nationalization. In West Germany, which has outlawed the
Communist Party, the Social Democratic Party, having officially rejected its
Marxist programs, is convincingly proving its respectability. This is the
situation in the leading industrial countries of the West. In the East, the
gradual reduction of direct political controls testifies to increasing reliance
on the effectiveness of technological controls as instruments of domination.
As for the strong Communist parties in France and Italy, they bear witness
to the general trend of circumstances by adhering to a minimum program which
shelves the revolutionary seizure of power and com- plies with the rules of
the parliamentary game.
However, while
it is incorrect to consider the French and Italian parties "foreign"
in the sense of being sustained by a foreign power, there is an unintended
kernel of truth in this propaganda: they are foreign inasmuch as they are
witnesses of a past (or future?) history in the present reality. If they have
agreed to work within the framework of the established system, it is not merely
on tactical grounds and as short-range strategy,
but
because their social base has been weakened and their objectives altered by
the transformation of the capitalist system (as have the objectives of the
Soviet Union which has endorsed this change in policy). These national Communist
parties play the historical role of legal opposition parties "condemned"
to be non-radical. They testify to the depth and scope of capitalist integration,
and to the conditions which make the qualitative difference of conflicting
interests appear as quantitative differences within the established society.
No analysis
in depth seems to be necessary in order to find the reasons for these developments.
As to the West: the former conflicts within society are modified and arbitrated
under the double (and interrelated) impact of technical progress and
international communism. Class struggles are attenuated and "imperialist
contradictions" suspended before the threat from without. Mobilized against
this threat, capitalist society shows an internal union and cohesion unknown
at previous stages of industrial civilization. It is a cohesion on
very material grounds; mobilization against the enemy works as a mighty stimulus
of production and employment, thus sustaining the high standard of
living.
On these grounds, there
arises a universe of administration in which depressions are controlled
and conflicts stabilized by the beneficial effects of growing productivity
and threatening nuclear war. Is this stabilization "temporary" in
the sense that it does not affect the roots of the conflicts which
Marx found in the capitalist mode of production (contradiction between
private ownership of the means of production and social productivity),
or is it a transformation of the antagonistic structure itself,
which resolves the contradictions by making them tolerable? And, if the second
alternative is true, how does it change the relationship between capitalism
and socialism which made the latter appear,
the
historical negation of the former?
Containment
of Social Change
The
classical Marxian theory envisages the transition from capitalism to socialism
as a political revolution: the proletariat destroys the political apparatus
of capitalism but retains the technological apparatus, subjecting it
to socialization, There is continuity in the revolution: technological rationality,
freed from irrational restrictions and destructions, sustains and consummates
itself in the new society, It is interesting to read a Soviet Marxist statement
on this continuity, which is of such vital importance for the notion of socialism
as the determinate negation of capitalism:[1]
"(1)
Though the development of technology is subject to the economic laws of each
social formation, it does not, like other economic factors, end with the cessation
of the laws of the formation. When in the process of revolution the old relations
of production are broken up, technology remains and, subordinated to the economic
laws of the new economic formation, continues to develop further, with added
speed, (2) Contrary to the development of the economic basis in antagonistic
societies, technology does not develop through leaps but by a gradual accumulation
of elements of a new quality, while the elements of the old quality disappear,
(3) [irrelevant in this context],”
In
advanced capitalism, technical rationality is embodied, in spite of its irrational
use, in the productive apparatus, This applies not only to mechanized plants,
tools, and exploitation of resources, but also to the mode of labor as adaptation
to and handling of the machine process, as arranged by "scientific management,"
Neither nationalization nor socialization alter by themselves this
physical embodiment of technological rationality; on the contrary, the latter
remains a precondition
for the socialist development of all productive forces.
To be sure, Marx held that
organization and direction of the productive apparatus by the "immediate
producers" would introduce a qualitative change in the technical
continuity: namely, production toward the satisfaction of freely developing
individual needs. However, to the degree to which the established technical
apparatus engulfs the public and private existence in all spheres of society-that
is, be- comes the medium of control and cohesion in a political universe which
incorporates the laboring classes-to that degree would the qualitative change
involve a change in the technological structure itself. And such change
would presuppose that the laboring classes are alienated from this
universe in their very existence, that their consciousness is that of the
total impossibility to continue to exist in this universe, so that the need
for qualitative change is a matter of life and death. Thus, the negation exists
prior to the change itself, the notion that the liberating historical
forces develop within the established society is a cornerstone of Marxian
theory.[2]
Now it is precisely this
new consciousness, this .space within," the space for the transcending
historical practice, which is being barred by a society in which subjects
as well as objects constitute instrumentalities in a whole that has its raison
d' etre in the accomplishments of its overpowering productivity.
Its supreme promise is an ever-more-comfortable life for an ever-growing number
of people who, in a strict sense, cannot imagine a qualitatively different
universe of discourse and action, for the capacity to contain and manipulate
subversive imagination and effort is an integral part of the given society.
Those whose life is the hell of the Affluent Society are kept in line by a
brutality which revives medieval and early modem practices. For the other,
less underprivileged people, society takes care of the
need for liberation by satisfying the needs which make servitude palatable
and perhaps even unnoticeable, and it accomplishes this fact in the process
of production itself. Under its impact, the laboring classes in the advanced
areas of industrial civilization are undergoing a decisive transformation,
which has become the subject of a vast sociological research. I shall enumerate
the main factors of this transformation:
(1)
Mechanization is increasingly reducing the quantity and intensity of physical
energy expended in labor. This evolution is of great bearing on the Marxian
concept of the worker (proletarian). To Marx, the proletarian is primarily
the manual laborer who expends and exhausts his physical energy in the work
process, even if he works with machines. The purchase and use of this physical
energy, under sub-human conditions, for the private appropriation of surplus-value
entailed the revolting inhuman aspects of exploitation; the Marxian notion
denounces the physical pain and misery of labor. This is the material, tangible
element in wage slavery and alienation-the physiological and biological dimension
of classical capitalism.
"Pendant les siecles passes, une cause importante d'alienation
residait dans Ie fait que l'etre humain pretait son individualite biologique
a l'organisation technique: il etait porteur d'outils; les ensembles techniques
ne pouvaient se constituer qu'en incorporant l’homme comme porteur d'outils.
Le caractere deformant de la profession etait a la fois psychique et somatique."3
Now the ever-more-complete mechanization of labor in advanced capitalism,
while sustaining exploitation, modifies the attitude and the status of the
exploited, Within the technological ensemble, mechanized work in which automatic
and semi-automatic reactions fill the larger part (if not the whole) of labor
time remains, as a life-long occupation, exhausting, stupefying, inhuman slavery-even
more exhausting because of increased speed-up, control of the machine operators
(rather than of the product), and isolation of the workers from each other4. To be sure, this form
of drudgery is expressive of arrested, partial automation, of the coexistence
of automated, semi-automated, and non-automated sections within the same plant,
but even under these conditions, "for muscular fatigue technology has
substituted tension and/or mental effort,"5 For the more advanced automated plants,
the transformation of physical energy into technical and mental skills is
emphasized:
“…skills of the
head rather than of the hand, of the logician rather than the craftsman; of
nerve rather than muscle; of the pilot rather than the manual worker; of the
maintenance man rather than the operator,"6
This kind of
masterly enslavement is not essentially different from that of the typist,
the bank teller, the high-pressure salesman or saleswoman, and the television
announcer. Standardization and the
routine assimilate productive and non-productive jobs, The proletarian of
the previous stages of capitalism was indeed the beast of burden, by the labor
of his body procuring the necessities and luxuries of life while living in
filth and poverty, Thus he was the living denial of his society.7
In contrast, the organized worker in the advanced areas
of the technological society lives this denial less conspicuously and, like
the other human objects of the social division of labor, he is being incorporated
into the technological community of the administered population, Moreover,
in the most successful areas of automation, some sort of technological community
seems to integrate the human atoms at work, The machine seems to instill some
drugging rhythm in the operators:
"It
is generally agreed that interdependent motions performed by
a group of persons which follow a rhythmic pattern yield satisfaction-quite
apart from what is being accomplished by the motions";8
and
the sociologist-observer believes this to be a reason for the gradual development
of a "general climate" more "favorable both to production and
to certain important kinds of human satisfaction," He speaks of the "growth
of a strong in-group feeling in each crew" and quotes one worker as stating:
"All in all we are in the swing of things. . ."9
The
phrase admirably expresses the change in mechanized enslavement: things swing
rather than oppress, and they swing the human instrument-not only its body
but also its mind and even its soul, A remark by Sartre elucidates the depth
of the process:
"Aux premiers temps des machines semi-automatiques,
des enquetes ont montre que les ouvrieres specialisees se laissaient aller,
en travaillant, a une reverie d'ordre sexuel, elles se rappellaient la chambre,
le lit, la nuit, tout ce qui ne concerne que la personne dans la solitude
du couple ferme sur soi. Mais c' est
1a machine en elle qui revait de caresses. . . "10
The
machine process in the technological universe breaks the innermost privacy
of freedom and joins sexuality and labor in one unconscious, rhythmic automatism-a
process which parallels the assimilation of jobs.
(2)
The assimilating trend shows forth in the occupational stratification. In
the key industrial establishments, the "blue-collar" work force
declines in relation to the "white- collar" element; the number
of non-production workers increases11. This
quantitative change refers back to a change in the character of the basic
instruments of production12. At the
advanced stage of mechanization, as part of the technological reality, the
machine is not
"one unite absolue, roais seulement une realite technique
individualisee, ouverte selon deux voies: celle de la relation aux elements,
et celle des relations interindividuelles dans l'ensemble technique."13
To
the extent to which the machine becomes itself a system of mechanical tools
and relations and thus extends far beyond the individual work process, it
asserts its larger dominion by reducing the "professional autonomy. of
the laborer and integrating him with other professions which suffer and direct
the technical ensemble. To be sure, the former "professional" autonomy
of the laborer was rather his professional enslavement. But this specific
mode of enslavement was at the same time the source of his specific, professional
power of negation-the power to stop a process which threatened him with annihilation
as a human being. Now the laborer is losing the professional autonomy which
made him a member of a class set off from the other occupational groups because
it embodied the refutation of the established society.
The
technological change which tends to do away with the machine as individual
instrument of production, as "absolute unit, - seems to cancel the
Marxian notion of the organic composition of capital" and with it the
theory of the creation of surplus value. According to Marx, the machine never
creates value but merely transfers its own value to the product, while surplus
value remains the result of the exploitation of living labor. The machine
is embodiment of human labor power, and through it, past labor (dead labor)
preserves itself and determines living labor. Now automation seems to alter
qualitatively the relation between dead and living labor; it tends toward
the point where productivity is determined "by the machines, and not
by the individual output."14
Moreover, the very measurement of individual output
becomes impossible:
“Automation
in its largest sense means, in effect, the end of measurement
of work. .
. . With automation, you can't measure output of a
single man; you now have to measure simply equipment utilization. If that
is generalized as a kind of concept . . . there is no longer, for example,
any reason at all to pay a man by the piece or pay him by the hour,- that
is to say, there is no more reason to keep up the "dual pay system"
of salaries and wages.”15
Daniel
Bell. the author of this report, goes further; he links this technological
change to the historical system of industrialization itself: the meaning
of
industrialization
did not arise with the introduction of factories, it "arose out of the
measurement of work. It's when work can be measured, when you can hitch
a man to the job. when you can put a harness on him. and measure his output
in terms of a single piece and pay him by the piece or by the hour. that you
have
got modern industrialization.16
What
is at stake in these technological changes is far more than a pay system.
the relation of the worker to other classes, and the organization of
work. What is at stake is the compatibility of technical progress
with the very institutions in which industrialization developed.
(3)
These changes in the character of work and the instruments of production
change the attitude and the consciousness of the laborer, which become
manifest in the widely discussed "social and cultural integration"
of the laboring class with capitalist society. Is this a change in
consciousness only? The affirmative answer, frequently given by Marxists.
seems strangely inconsistent. Is such a fundamental change in consciousness
understandable without assuming a corresponding change in the "societal
existence"? Granted even a high degree of ideological independence,
the links which tie this change to the transformation of the productive
process militate against such an interpretation. Assimilation in needs and
aspirations, in the standard of living, In leisure activities, in politics
derives from an integration in the plant itself, in the material process
of production. It is certainly questionable whether one can speak of
"voluntary integration"
(Serge Mallet) in any other than an ironical sense. In the present situation.
the negative features of automation
are predominant: speed-up, technological unemployment, strengthening of the
position of management, increasing impotence and resignation on the part of
the workers. The chances of promotion decline as management prefers engineers and
college graduates.17
However,
there are other trends. The same technological organization
which makes for a mechanical community at work also generates a larger interdependence
which18 integrates
the worker with the plant. One notes an "eagerness" on the part
of the workers "to share in the solution of production problems,"
a "desire to join actively in applying their own brains to technical
and production problems which clearly fitted in with the technology."19
In
some of the technically most advanced establishments,
the workers even show a vested interest in the establishment-a frequently
observed effect of "workers' participation" in capitalist enterprise.
A provocative description, referring to the highly Americanized Caltex refineries
at Ambes, France, may serve to characterize this trend. The workers of the
plant are conscious of the links which attach them to the enterprise:
Liens professionnels, liens sociaux, liens materiels: le
metier appris dans la raffinerie, I'habitude des rapports de production qui
s'y sont etablis, les multiples avantages sociaux qui, en cas de mort subite,
de maladie grave, d'incapacite de travail, de vieillesse enfin, lui sont assures
par sa seule appartenance a la firme, prolongeant au-dela de la periode productive
de leur vie la si1rete des lendemains. Ainsi, la notion de ce contrat vivant
et indestructible avec la 'Caltex' les amene a se preoccuper, avec une attention
et une lucidite inattendue, de la gestion financiere de l'entreprise. Les
delegues aux Comites d' entreprise epluchent la comptabilite de la societe avec le soin jaloux qu'y accorderaient des
actionnaires consciencieux. La direction de 1a Caltex peut certes se frotter
les mains lorsque les syndicats acceptent de surseoir A leurs revendications
de salaires en presence des besoins d'investissements nouveaux. Mais elle
commence a manifester les plus ‘legitimes' inquietudes lorsque, prenant au
mot les bilans truques de la filiale francaise, ils s'inquietent des marches
'desavantageux' passes par celles-ci et poussent l'audace jusqu'a contester
les prix de revient et suggerer des propositions economiques !20
(4)
The new technological work-world thus enforces a weakening of the negative
position of the working class: the latter no longer appears to be the living
contradiction to the established society. This trend is strengthened by the
effect of the technological organization of production on the other side of
the fence: on management and direction. Domination is transfigured into administration.21 The capitalist bosses
and owners are losing their identity as responsible agents; they are assuming
the function of bureaucrats in a corporate machine. Within the vast hierarchy
of executive and managerial boards extending far beyond the individual establishment
into the scientific laboratory and research institute, the national government
and national purpose, the tangible source of exploitation disappears behind
the facade of objective rationality. Hatred and frustration are deprived of
their specific target, and the technological veil conceals the reproduction
of inequality and enslavement.22
With technical progress as its instrument, unfreedom-in the sense of man's
subjection to his productive apparatus-is perpetuated and intensified in the
form of many liberties and comforts. The novel feature is the overwhelming
rationality in this irrational enterprise, and the depth of the preconditioning
which shapes the instinctual drives and aspirations of the individuals and
obscures the difference between false and true consciousness. For in reality,
neither the utilization of administrative rather than physical controls (hunger,
personal dependence, force), nor the change in the character of heavy work,
nor the assimilation of occupational classes, nor the equalization in the
sphere of consumption compensate for the fact that the decisions over life
and death, over personal and national security are made at places over which
the individuals have no control. The slaves of developed industrial civilization
are sublimated slaves, but they are slaves, for slavery is determined
« pas par I' obeissance. ni par la rudesse des labeurs,
mais par le statu d'instrument et la reduction de l’homme a l’etat de chose,"23
This
is the pure form of servitude: to exist as an instrument, as
a thing, And this mode of existence is not abrogated if the thing is
animated and chooses its material and intellectual food, if it does not feel
its being-a-thing, if it is a pretty, clean, mobile thing, Conversely, as
reification tends to become totalitarian by virtue of its
technological form, the organizers and administrators themselves become increasingly
dependent on the machinery which they organize and administer, And this mutual
dependence is no longer the dialectical relationship between Master and Servant,
which has been broken in the struggle for mutual recognition, but rather a
vicious circle which encloses both the Master and the Servant, Do the technicians
rule, or is their rule that of the others, who rely on the technicians
as their planners and executors?
“,
, , the pressures of today's highly technological arms
race have taken the initiative and the power to make the crucial decisions
out of the hands of responsible government officials and placed
it in the hands of technicians, planners and scientists employed by
vast industrial empires and charged with responsibility for their employers'
interests, It is their job to dream up new weapons systems and persuade the
military that the future of their military profession, as well as the
country. depends upon buying what they have dreamed up."24
As
the productive establishments rely on the military for self-preservation and
growth, so the military relies on the corporations "not only for
their weapons, but also for knowledge of what kind of weapons they need, how
much they will cost, and how long it will take to
get them."25
A vicious circle seems indeed the
proper image of a society which is self-expanding and self-perpetuating in
its own preestablished direction-driven by the growing needs which it generates
and, at the same time, contains.
Prospects of
Containment
Is there any
prospect that this chain of growing productivity and repression may be broken?
An answer would re- quire an attempt to project contemporary developments
into the future, assuming a relatively normal evolution, that is, neglecting
the very real possibility of a nuclear war. On this assumption, the Enemy
would remain "permanent"-that is, communism would continue to coexist
with capitalism. At the same time, the latter would continue to be capable
of maintaining and even increasing the standard of living for an increasing
part of the population-in spite of and through intensified production of the
means of destruction, and methodical waste of resources and faculties. This
capability has asserted itself in spite of and through two World Wars and
immeasurable physical and intellectual regression brought about by the fascist
systems.
The material base for this
capability would continue to be available in
( a) the growing productivity
of labor (technical progress);
(b) the rise in the birth
rate of the underlying population
(c) the permanent defense economy;
(d) the economic-political
integration of the capitalist countries, and the building up of their relations
with the underdeveloped areas.
But the continued conflict between the productive capabilities of society
and their destructive and oppressive utilization would necessitate intensified
efforts to impose the requirements of the apparatus on the population-to get
rid of excess capacity, to create the need for buying the goods that must
be profitably sold, and the desire to work for their production and promotion.
The system thus tends toward both total administration and total dependence
on administration by ruling public and private managements, strengthening
the preestablished harmony between the interest of the big public and private
corporations and that of their customers and servants. Neither partial nationalization
nor extended participation of labor in management and profit would by themselves
alter this system of domination-as long as labor itself remains a prop and
affirmative force.
There
are centrifugal tendencies, from within and from without. One of them is inherent
in technical progress itself, namely, automation. I suggested that
expanding automation is more than quantitative growth of mechanization-that
it is a change in the character of the basic productive forces.26 It seems that automation to the limits
of technical possibility is incompatible with a society based on the private
exploitation of human labor power in the process of production. Almost a century
before automation became a reality, Marx envisaged its explosive prospects:
As
large-sca1e industry advances, the creation of real wealth depends less on
the labor time and the quantity of labor expended ~ on
the power of the instrumentalities (Agentien) set in motion during
the labor time. These instrumentalities, and their powerful effectiveness,
are in no proportion to the immediate labor time which their production requires;
their effectiveness rather depends on the attained level of science and technological
progress; in other words, on the application of this science to production.
. . . Human labor then no longer appears as enclosed in the process of production-man
rather relates himself to the process of production as supervisor and regulator
(Wächter und Regulator). . . . He stands outside of the process
of production instead of being the principal agent in the process of production.
. . . In this transformation, the great pillar of production and wealth is
no longer the immediate labor performed by man him- self, nor his labor time,
but the appropriation of his own universal productivity (Produktivkraft),
i.e., his knowledge and his mastery of nature through his societal existence-in
one word: the development of the societal individual (des gesellschaftlichen
Individuums). The theft of another man's labor time, on
which the [social] wealth still rests today, then appears as a miserable
basis compared with the new basis which large-scale industry itself has created.
As soon as human labor, in its immediate form, has ceased to be the great
source of wealth, labor time will cease, and must of necessity cease to be
the measure of wealth, and the exchange value must of necessity cease to be
the measure of use value. The surplus labor of the mass [of the population]
has thus ceased to be the condition for the development of social wealth (des
allgemeinen Reichtums), and the idleness of the few has ceased to be the
condition for the development of the universal intellectual faculties of man.
The mode of production which rests on the exchange value thus collapses. .
.27
Automation indeed
appears to be the great catalyst of advanced industrial society. It is an
explosive or non-explosive catalyst in the material base of qualitative change,
the technical instrument of the turn from quantity to quality. For the social
process of automation expresses the transformation, or rather transubstantiation
of labor power, in which the latter, separated from the individual, becomes
an independent producing object and thus a subject itself.
Automation, once it became
the process of material production, would revolutionize the whole society.
The reification of human labor power, driven to perfection, would shatter
the reified form by cutting the chain that ties the individual to the machinery-the
mechanism through which his own labor enslaves him. Complete automation in
the realm of necessity would open the dimension of free time as the one in
which man's private and societal existence would constitute itself.
This would be the historical transcendence toward a new civilization.
At the present
stage of advanced capitalism, organized labor rightly opposes automation without
compensating employment. It insists on the extensive utilization of human
labor power in material production, and thus opposes technical progress. However,
in doing so, it also opposes the more efficient utilization of capital; it
hampers intensified efforts to raise the productivity of labor. In other words,
continued arrest of automation may weaken the competitive national and international
position of capital, cause a long- range depression, and consequently reactivate
the conflict of class interests.
This possibility
becomes more realistic as the contest between capitalism and communism shifts
from the military to the social and economic Held. By the power of total administration,
automation in the Soviet system can proceed more rapidly once a certain technical
level has been attained. This threat to its competitive international position
would compel the Western world to accelerate rationalization of the productive
process. Such rationalization encounters stiff resistance on the part of labor,
but resistance which is not accompanied by political radicalization. In the
United States at least, the leadership of labor in its aims and means does
not go beyond the framework common to the national and group interest, with
the latter submitting or subjected to the former.
These centrifugal forces are still manageable within this framework.
Here, too, the
declining proportion of human labor power
in the productive process means a decline in political power of the opposition,
In view of the increasing weight of the white-collar element in this process,
political radicalization would have to be accompanied by the emergence of
an independent political consciousness and action among the white-collar groups-a
rather unlikely development in advanced industrial society, The stepped-up
drive to organize the growing white-collar element in the industrial unions,28 if successful at all, may result in a
growth of trade union consciousness of these groups, but hardly in their political
radicalization.
"Politically,
the presence of more white-collar workers in labor unions will give liberal
and labor spokesmen a chance more truth- fully to identify 'the interests
of labor' with those of the community as a whole, The mass base of labor as
a pressure group will be further extended, and labor spokesmen will inevitably
be involved in more far-reaching bargains over the national political economy,"29
Under
these circumstances, the prospects for a streamlined containment of the centrifugal
tendencies depend primarily on the ability of the vested interests to adjust
themselves and their economy to the requirements of the Welfare State. Vastly
increased government spending and direction, planning on a national and international
scope, an enlarged foreign aid program, comprehensive social security, public
works on a grand scale, perhaps even partial nationalization belong to these
requirements.30 I believe that the dominant interests
will gradually and hesitantly accept these requirements and entrust their
prerogatives to a more effective power.
Turning now to the prospects
for the containment of social change in the other system of industrial civilization,
in Soviet society,31
the discussion is from the outset con- fronted with a double incomparability:
(a) chronologically, Soviet society is at an earlier stage of industrialization,
with large sectors still at the pre-technological stage, and (b) structurally,
its economic and its political institutions are essentially different (total
nationalization, and dictatorship).
The interconnection
between the two aspects aggravates the difficulties of the analysis. The historical
backwardness not only enables but compels Soviet industrialization to proceed
without planned waste and obsolescence, without the restrictions on productivity
imposed by the interests of private profit, and with planned satisfaction
of still unfulfilled vital needs after, and perhaps even simultaneously with,
the priorities of military and political needs.
Is this greater
rationality of industrialization only the token and advantage of historical
backwardness, likely to disappear once the advanced level is reached? Is it
tile same historical backwardness which, on the other hand, enforces -under
the conditions of the competitive coexistence with advanced capitalism-the
total development and control of all resources by a dictatorial regime? And,
after having attained the goal of "catching up and overtaking,"
would Soviet society then be able to liberalize the totalitarian controls
to the point where a qualitative change could take place?
The argument
from historical backwardness-according to which liberation must, under the
prevailing conditions of material and intellectual immaturity, necessarily
be the work of force and administration-is not only the core of Soviet Marxism,
but also that of the theoreticians of
"educational dictatorship" from Plato to Rousseau. It is easily
ridiculed but hard to refute because it has the merit to acknowledge. without
much hypocrisy, the conditions (material and intellectual) which serve to
prevent genuine and intelligent self- determination.
Moreover,
the argument debunks the repressive ideology of freedom. according to which
human liberty can blossom forth in a life of toil. poverty, and stupidity.
Indeed. society must first create the material prerequisites of freedom for
all its members before it can be a free society; it must first create the
wealth before being able to distribute it according to the freely developing
needs of the individual; it must first enable its slaves to learn and see
and think before they know what is going on and what they themselves can do
to change it. And, to the degree to which the slaves have
been preconditioned to exist as slaves and be content
in that role, their liberation necessarily appears to come from with- out
and from above. They must be "forced to be free." to "see objects
as they are, and sometimes as they ought to appear." they must be shown
the "good road" they are in search of.32
But
with all its truth, the argument cannot answer the time-honored question:
who educates the educators, and where is the proof
that they are in possession of "the good?"
The question is not invalidated by arguing that it is equally applicable to
certain democratic forms of government where the fateful decisions on what
is good for the nation are made by elected representatives (or rather endorsed
by elected representatives )-elected under conditions of
effective
and freely accepted indoctrination. Still. the only
possible excuse (it is weak enough!) for "educational dictatorship"
is that the terrible risk which it involves may not be more terrible than the risk
which the great liberal as well as the authoritarian societies are taking
now, nor may the costs be much higher.
However, the dialectical
logic insists, against the language of brute facts and ideology, that the
slaves must be free for their liberation before they can become free,
and that the end must be operative in the means to attain it. Marx's proposition
that the liberation of the working class must be the action of the working
class itself states this a priori. Socialism must become reality with
the first act of the revolution because it must already be in the consciousness
and action of those who carried the revolution.
True, there is a "first
phase" of socialist construction during which the new society is "still
stamped with the birth marks of the old society from whose womb it emerges,"33 as but
the qualitative change from the old to the new society occurred when this
phase began. According to Marx, the "second phase" is literally
constituted in the first phase. The qualitatively new mode of life generated
by the new mode of production appears in the socialist revolution, which is
the end and at the end of the capitalist system. Socialist construction
begins with the first phase of the revolution.
By the same
token, the transition from "to each according to his work" to "to
each according to his needs" is determined by the first phase---not
only by the creation of the technological and material base, but also (and
this is decisive!) by the mode in which it is created. Control of the
productive process by the "immediate producers" is supposed to initiate
the development which distinguishes the history of free men from the prehistory
of man. This is a Society in which the former objects of productivity first
become the human individuals who plan and
use the instruments of their labor for the realization of their own humane
needs and faculties. For the first time in history, men would act freely and
collectively under and against the necessity which limits their freedom and
their humanity. Therefore all repression imposed by necessity would be truly
self- imposed necessity. In contrast to this conception, the actual development
in present-day communist society postpones ( or is compelled to postpone,
by the international situation) the qualitative change to the second phase,
and the transition from capitalism to socialism appears, in spite of the revolution,
still as quantitative change. The enslavement of man by the instruments of
his labor continues in a highly rationalized and vastly efficient and promising
form.
The
situation of hostile coexistence may explain the terroristic features of Stalinist
industrialization, but it also set in motion the forces which tend to perpetuate
technical progress as the instrument of domination; the means prejudice the
end. Again assuming that no nuclear warfare or other catastrophe cuts off
its development, technical progress would make for continued increase in the
standard of living and for continued liberalization of controls. The nationalized
economy could exploit the productivity of labor and capital without structural
resistance34 while considerably reducing
working hours and augmenting the comforts of life. And it could accomplish
all this without abandoning the hold of total administration over the people.
There is no reason to assume that technical progress plus nationalization
will make for "automatic" liberation and release of the negating
forces. On the contrary, the contradiction between the growing productive
forces and their enslaving organization-openly admitted as a feature of Soviet
socialist development even by Stalin35-is
likely to
flatten out rather than to aggravate.
The more the rulers are
capable of delivering the goods of consumption, the more firmly will the underlying
population be tied to the various ruling bureaucracies.
But while these
prospects for the containment of qualitative change in the Soviet system seem
to be parallel to those in advanced capitalist society, the socialist base
of production introduces a decisive difference.
In the Soviet system, the organization of the productive process certainly
separates the "immediate producers" (the laborers) from control
over the means of production and thus makes for class distinctions at the
very base of the system. This separation was established by political decision
and power after the brief "heroic period" of the Bolshevik Revolution,
and has been perpetuated ever since. And yet it is not the motor of the productive
process itself; it is not built into this process as is the division between
capital and labor, derived from private ownership of the means of production.
Consequently, the ruling strata are themselves separable from the productive
process-that is, they are replaceable without exploding the basic institutions
of society.
This is the
half-truth in the Soviet-Marxist thesis that the prevailing contradictions
between the “lagging production relations and the character of the productive
forces" can be resolved without explosion, and that "conformity"
between the two factors can occur through "gradual change."36
The
other half of the truth is that quantitative change would still have to turn
into qualitative change, into thee disappearance of the State, the Party,
the Plan, etc. as Independent powers superimposed on the individuals. Inasmuch
as this change would leave the material base of society (the nationalized
productive process) intact, it would be confined
to a political revolution. If it could lead to self-determination at
the very base of human existence, namely in the dimension of necessary labor,
it would be the most radical and most complete revolution in history. Distribution
of the necessities of life regardless of work performance, reduction of working
time to a minimum, universal all-sided education toward exchangeability of
functions-these are the preconditions but not the contents of self-determination.
While the creation of these preconditions may still be the result of superimposed
administration, their establishment would mean the end of this administration.
To be sure, a mature and free industrial society would continue to depend
on a division of labor which involves inequality of functions. Such inequality
is necessitated by genuine social needs, technical requirements, and the physical
and mental differences among the individuals. However, the executive and supervisory
functions would no longer carry the privilege of ruling the life of others
in some particular interest. The transition to such a state is a revolutionary
rather than evolutionary process, even on the foundation of a fully nationalized
and planned
economy.
Can
one assume that the communist system, in its established forms, would develop
(or rather be forced to develop by Virtue of the international contest)
the conditions which would make for such a transition? There are strong arguments
against this assumption. One emphasizes the powerful resistance which the
entrenched bureaucracy would offer-a resistance which finds its raison
d’etre precisely on the same grounds that impel the drive for creating
the preconditions for liberation, namely, the life-and-death competition with
the capitalist world.
One
can dispense with the notion of an innate "power- drive" in human
nature. This is a highly dubious psychological concept and grossly inadequate
for the analysis of societal developments. The question is not whether the
communist bureaucracies would "give up" their privileged position
once the level of a possible qualitative change has been reached, but whether
they will be able to prevent the attainment of this level. In order to do
so, they would have to arrest material and intellectual growth at a point
where domination still is rational and profitable, where the under- lying
population can still be tied to the job and to the interest of the state or
other established institutions. Again, the decisive factor here seems to be
the global situation of co-existence, which has long since become a factor
in the internal situation of the two opposed societies. The need for
the all-out utilization of technical progress, and for survival by virtue
of a superior standard of living may prove stronger than the resistance of
the vested bureaucracies.
I
should like to add a few remarks on the often-heard opinion that the new development
of the backward countries might not only alter the prospects of the advanced
industrial countries, but also constitute a "third force" that may
grow into a relatively independent power. In terms of the preceding discussion:
is there any evidence that the former colonial or semi-colonial areas might
adopt a way of industrialization essentially different from capitalism and
present- day communism? Is there anything in the indigenous culture and tradition
of these areas which might indicate such an alternative? I shall confine my
remarks to models of backwardness already in the process of industrialization-that
is, to countries where industrialization coexists with an unbroken pre- and
anti-industrial culture (India, Egypt).
These
countries enter upon the process of industrialization with a population untrained
in the values of self-propel- ling productivity, efficiency, and technological
rationality. In other words, with a vast majority of population which has
not yet been transformed into a labor force separated from the means
of production. Do these conditions favor a new confluence of industrialization
and liberation-an essentially different mode of industrialization which would
build the productive apparatus not only in accord with the vital needs of
the underlying population, but also with the aim of pacifying the struggle
for existence?
Industrialization
in these backward areas does not take place in a vacuum. It occurs in a historical
situation in which the social capital required for primary accumulation must
be obtained largely from without, from the capitalist or communist bloc-or
from both. Moreover, there is a widespread presumption that remaining independent
would require rapid industrialization and attainment of a level of
productivity which would assure at least relative autonomy in competition
with the two giants.
In these circumstances,
the transformation of under- developed into industrial societies must as quickly
as possible discard the pre-technological forms. This is especially so in
countries where even the most vital needs of the population are far from being
satisfied, where the terrible standard of living calls first of all for quantities
en masse, for mechanized and standardized mass production and distribution.
And in these same countries, the dead weight of pre-technological and even
pre-'bourgeois" customs and conditions offers a strong resistance to
such a superimposed development. The machine process (as social process) requires
obedience to a system of anonymous powers-total secularization and the destruction
of values and institutions whose de-sanctification has hardly begun. Can one
reasonably assume that, under the impact of the two great systems of total
technological administration, the dissolution of this resistance will proceed
in liberal and democratic forms? That the underdeveloped countries can make
the historical leap from the pre-technological to the post-technological society,
in which the mastered technological apparatus may provide the basis for
a genuine democracy? On the contrary, it rather seems that the superimposed
development of these countries will bring about a period of total administration
more violent and more rigid than that traversed by the advanced societies
which can build on the achievements of the liberalistic era. To sum up: the
backward areas are likely to succumb either to one of the various forms of
neo-colonialism, or to a more or less terroristic system of primary accumulation.
However,
another alternative seems possible.37
If industrialization and the introduction of technology in the back- ward
countries encounter strong resistance from the indigenous and traditional
modes of life and labor-a resistance which is not abandoned even at the very
tangible prospect of a better and easier life-could this pre-technological
tradition itself become the source of progress and industrialization?
Such
indigenous progress would demand a planned policy which, instead of superimposing
technology on the traditional modes of life and labor, would extend and improve
them on their own grounds, eliminating the oppressive and exploitative forces
(material and religious) which made them incapable of assuring the development
of a human existence. Social revolution, agrarian reform, and reduction of
over-population would be prerequisites, but not industrialization after the
pattern of the advanced societies. Indigenous progress seems indeed possible
in areas where the natural resources, if freed from suppressive encroachment,
are still sufficient not only for subsistence but also for a human life. And
where they are not, could they not be made sufficient by the gradual and piecemeal
aid of technology-within the framework of the traditional forms?
If
this is the case, then conditions would prevail which do not exist in the
old and advanced industrial societies (and never existed there )-namely, the
"immediate producers" themselves would have the chance to create,
by their own labor and leisure, their own progress and determine its rate
and direction. Self-determination would proceed from the base, and work for
the necessities could transcend itself toward work for gratification.
But
even under these abstract assumptions, the brute limits of self-determination
must be acknowledged. The initial revolution which, by abolishing mental and
material exploitation, is to establish the prerequisites for the new development,
is hardly conceivable as spontaneous action. Moreover, indigenous progress
would presuppose a change in the policy of the two great industrial power
blocs which today shape the world-abandonment of neo-colonialism in all its
forms. At present, there is no indication of such a change.
The Welfare and Warfare State
By
way of summary: the prospects of containment of change, offered by the politics
of technological rationality, depend on the prospects of the Welfare State.
Such a state seems capable of raising the standard of administered living,
a capability inherent in all advanced industrial societies where the streamlined
technical apparatus-set up as a separate power over and above the individuals-depends
for its functioning on the intensi:6ed development and expansion of productivity.
Under such conditions, decline of freedom and opposition is not a matter of
moral or intellectual deterioration or corruption. It is rather an objective
societal process insofar as the production and distribution of an increasing
quantity of goods and services make compliance a rational technological attitude.
However,
with all its rationality, the Welfare State is a state of unfreedom because
its total administration is systematic restriction of (a) "technically"
available free time;38 (b) the
quantity and quality of goods and services "technically" available
for vital individual needs; (c) the intelligence (conscious and unconscious)
capable of comprehending and realizing the possibilities of self-determination.
Late industrial society has increased
rather than reduced the need for parasitical and alienated functions (for
the society as a whole, if not for the individual). Advertising, public relations,
indoctrination, planned obsolescence are no longer unproductive overhead costs
but rather elements of basic production costs. In order to be effective, such
production of socially necessary waste requires continuous rationalization-the
relentless utilization of advanced techniques and science. Consequently, a
rising standard of living is the almost unavoidable by-product of the politically
manipulated industrial society, once a certain level of backwardness has been
overcome. The growing productivity of labor creates an increasing surplus-product
which, whether privately or centrally appropriated and distributed, allows
an increased consumption-notwithstanding the increased diversion of productivity.
As long as this constellation prevails, it reduces the use-value of freedom;
there is no reason to insist on self-determination if the administered life
is the comfortable and even the "good" life. This is the rational
and material ground for the unification of opposites, for one-dimensional
political behavior. On this ground, the transcending political forces within
society are arrested, and qualitative change appears possible only as
a change from without.
Rejection
of the Welfare State on behalf of abstract ideas of freedom is hardly convincing.
The loss of the economic and political liberties which were the real achievement
of the preceding two centuries may seem slight damage in a state capable of
making the administered life secure and comfortable.39 If the individuals are satisfied to the
point of happiness with the goods and services handed down to them by the
administration, why should they insist on different institutions for a different
production of different goods and services? And if the individuals are pre-conditioned
so that the satisfying goods also include thoughts, feelings, aspirations,
why should they wish to think, feel, and imagine for themselves? True, the
material and mental commodities offered may be bad, wasteful, rubbish-but
Geist and knowledge are no telling arguments against satisfaction of
needs.
The
critique of the Welfare State in terms of liberalism and conservatism (with
or without the prefix "neo") rests, for its validity, on the existence
of the very conditions which the Welfare State has surpassed-namely, a lower
degree of social wealth and technology. The sinister aspects of this critique
show forth in the fight against comprehensive social legislation and adequate
government expenditures for services other than those of military defense.
Denunciation
of the oppressive capabilities of the Welfare State thus serves to protect
the oppressive capabilities of the society prior to the Welfare State.
At the most advanced stage of capitalism, this society is a system of subdued
pluralism, in which the competing institutions concur in solidifying the power
of the whole over the individual. Still, for the administered individual,
pluralistic administration is far better than total administration. One institution
might protect him against the other; one organization might mitigate the impact
of the other; possibilities of escape and redress can be calculated. The rule
of law, no matter how restricted, is still infinitely safer than rule above
or without law.
However,
in view of prevailing tendencies, the question must be raised whether this
form of pluralism does not accelerate the destruction of pluralism. Advanced
industrial society is indeed a system of countervailing powers. But these
forces cancel each other out in a higher unification- in the common interest
to defend and extend the established position, to combat the historical alternatives,
to contain qualitative change. The countervailing powers do not include those
which counter the whole.40
They tend to make the whole immune against negation from within as well as
without; the foreign policy of containment appears as an extension of the
domestic policy of containment.
The
reality of pluralism becomes ideological, deceptive. It seems to extend rather
than reduce manipulation and co-ordination, to promote rather than counteract
the fateful integration. Free institutions compete with authoritarian ones
in making the Enemy a deadly force within the system. And this deadly
force stimulates growth and initiative, not by virtue of the magnitude and
economic impact of the defense "sector," but by virtue of the fact
that the society as a whole becomes a defense society. For the Enemy is permanent.
He is not in the emergency situation but in the normal state of affairs. He
threatens in peace as much as in war (and per- haps more than in war); he
is thus being built into the system as a cohesive power.
Neither
the growing productivity nor the high standard of living depend on the threat
from without, but their use for the containment of social change and perpetuation
of servitude does. The Enemy is the common denominator of all
doing and undoing. And the Enemy is not identical with actual communism or
actual capitalism-he is. in both cases. the real spectre of liberation.
Once again: the insanity of the whole absolves
the particular insanities and turns the crimes against humanity into a rational
enterprise. When the people. aptly stimulated by the public and private authorities.
prepare for lives of total mobilization. they are sensible not only because
of the present Enemy. but also because of the investment and employment possibilities
in industry and entertainment. Even the most insane calculations are rational:
the annihilation of five million people is preferable to that of ten million.
twenty million. and so on. It is hopeless to argue that a civilization which
justifies its defense by such a calculus proclaims its own end.
Under these
circumstances. even the existing liberties and escapes fall in place within
the organized whole. At this stage of the regimented market. is competition
alleviating or intensifying the race for bigger and faster turnover and obsolescence?
Are the political parties competing for pacification or for a stronger and
more costly armament industry? Is the production of "affluence"
promoting or de- laying the satisfaction of still unfulfilled vital needs?
If the first alternatives are true. the contemporary form of pluralism would
strengthen the potential for the containment of qualitative change. and thus
prevent rather than impel the "catastrophe" of self-determination.
Democracy would appear to be the most efficient system of domination.
The image of
the Welfare State sketched in the preceding paragraphs is that of a historical
freak between organized capitalism and socialism, servitude and freedom, totalitarianism
and happiness. Its possibility is sufficiently indicated by prevalent tendencies
of technical progress, and sufficiently threatened
by explosive forces. The most powerful, of course,
is the danger that preparation for total nuclear war may
turn into its realization: the deterrent also serves to deter efforts to eliminate
the need for the deterrent. Other factors are at play which may preclude
the pleasant juncture of totalitarianism and happiness, manipulation and democracy,
heteronomy and autonomy-in short, the perpetuation of the preestablished harmony
between organized and spontaneous behavior, preconditioned and free thought,
expediency and conviction.
Even
the most highly organized capitalism retains the social need for private appropriation
and distribution of t as the regulator of the economy. That is, it continues
to link the realization of the general interest to that of particular vested
interests. In doing so, it continues to face the conflict between the growing
potential of pacifying the struggle for existence, and the need for intensifying
this struggle; between the progressive "abolition of labor" and
need for preserving labor as the source of profit. The conflict perpetuates
the inhuman existence of those who form the human base of the social pyramid-the
outsiders the poor, the unemployed and unemployable, the persecuted colored
races, the inmates of prisons and mental institutions.
In
contemporary communist societies, the enemy with- backwardness, and the legacy
of terror perpetuate the oppressive features of "catching up with and
surpassing" achievements of capitalism. The priority of the means r the
end is thereby aggravated-a priority which could broken only if pacification
is achieved-and capitalism and communism continue to compete without military
force, on a global scale and through global institutions. This pacification
would mean the emergence of a genuine world economy-the demise of the nation
state, the national interest, national business together with their international
alliances.
And
this is precisely the possibility against which the present world is mobilized:
L’ignorance et l’inconscience sont telles que les nationalismes
demeurent florissants. Ni l.armement ni l.industrie du XXe siecle ne permettent
aux patries d’assurer leur securite et leur vie sinon en ensembles
organises de poids mondial. dans l’ordre militaire et economique. Mais a l'Ouest
non plus qu’a l’Est, les croyances collectives n’assimilent les changements
reels. Les Grands forment leurs empires, ou en reparent les architectures
sans accepter les changements de regime economique et politique qui donneraient
efficacite et sens a l’une et a l’autre coalitions.
and:
Dupes de la nation et dupes de la classe, les masses souffrantes
sont partout engagees dans les duretes de conflits ou leurs seuls ennemis
sont des maitres qui emploient sciemment les mystifications de l’industrie
et du pouvoir,
La collusion de l'industrie moderne et du pouvoir territorialise
est un vice dont la realite est plus profonde que les institutions et les
structures capitalistes et communistes et qu'aucune dialectique necessaire
ne doit necessairement extirper.41
The
fateful interdependence of the only two "sovereign- social systems in
the contemporary world is expressive of the fact that the conflict between
progress and politics, between man and his masters has become total. When
capital- ism meets the challenge of communism, it meets its own capabilities:
spectacular development of all productive forces after the subordination of
the private interests in profitability which arrest such development. When
communism meets the challenge of capitalism, it too meets its own capabilities:
spectacular comforts, liberties, and alleviation of the burden of life. Both
systems have these capabilities distorted beyond recognition and, in both
cases, the reason is in the last analysis the same-the struggle against a
form of life which would dissolve the basis for domination.
[1] A. Zworikine, 'The
History of Technology as a Science and as a Branch of Learning; a Soviet
view," Technology and Culture. (Detroit: Wayne State
University Press, Winter 1961), p. 2.
[2] See p. 41.
3 "During the
past centuries, one important reason for alienation v:'8s that the human
being lent his biological individuality to the technical apparatus: he was
the bearer of tools; technical units could not be established without incorporating
man as bearer of tools into them, The nature of this occupation was such
that it was both psychologically and physiologically deforming in its effect,"
Gilbert Simondon, Du Mode d’existence des objets techniques (Paris:
Aubier, 1958), p, 103, note.
4 See Charles Denby,
"Workers Battle Automation" (New, and Letters, Detroit,
1900).
5 Charles R. Walker,
Toward the Automatic Factory (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1957),
p. XIX.
6 Ibid., p. 195.
7 One must insist
on the inner connection between the Marxian concepts of exploitation and
impoverishment in spite of later redefinitions, in which impoverishment
either becomes a cultural aspect, or relative to such an extent that it
applies also to the suburban home with automobile, television, etc. "Impoverishment"
connotes the absolute need and necessity of subverting Intolerable
conditions of existence, and such absolute need appears in the beginnings
of all revolution against the basic social institutions.
8 Charles R. Walker,
loc. cit., p. 104.
9 Ibid., p. 104
f.
10 "Shortly after
semi-automatic machines were introduced, investigations showed that female
skilled workers would allow themselves to lapse while working into a sexual
kind of daydream; they would recall the bedroom, the bed, the night and
all that concerns only the person within the solitude of the couple alone
with itself. But it was the machine in her which was dreaming of caresses.
. ." Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique de la raison dialectique,
tome I (Paris: Gallimard, 1960), p. 290.
11 Automation and Major Technological
Change: Impact on Union Size, Structure, and Function. (Industrial Union
Dept. AFL-CIO, Washingon, 1958) p. 5ff. Solomon Barkin, The Decline
of
the Labor Movement (Santa Barbara,
Center for the Study of Democratic Institutions, 1961), p. 10 ff
12 See p. 23.
13 "an absolute
unity, but only an individualized technical reality open in two directions,
that of the relation to the elements and that of the relation among the
individuals In the technical whole." Gilbert Simondon, loc. cit., p. 146.
14 Serge Mallet. in Arguments, no.
12-13, Paris 1958, p. 18.
15 Automation and
Major Technological Change, loc.
cit., p. 8.
16 Ibid.
17 Charles R. Walker.
loc. cit.., p. 97 ff. See also Ely Chinoy, Automobile Workers
and the American Dream. (Garden City: Doubleday, 1955) passim.
18 Floyd C. Mann and
L. Richard Hoffman, Automation and the Worker. A Study of Social Change
in Power Plants (New York. Henry Holt: 1960), p. 189.
19 Charles R. Walker,
loc. cit., p. 213 f.
20 "Professional,
social, material links: the skill they acquired in the refinery, the fact
that they got used to certain production relationships which were established
there; the manifold social benefits on which they can count in case of sudden
death, serious illness, incapacity to work, finally old age, merely because
they belong to the firm, extending their security beyond the productive
period of their lives. Thus the notion of a living and indestructible contract
with Caltex makes them think with unexpected attention and lucidity about the
financial management of the firm. The delegates to the "Comités d'entreprise"
examine and discuss the accounts of the company with the same jealous care
that conscientious shareholders would devote to it. The board of directors
of Caltex can certainly rub their hands with joy when the unions agree to
put off their salary demands because of the need for new investments. But
they begin to show signs of 1egitimate' anxiety when the delegates take
seriously faked balance sheets of the French branches and worry about disadvantageous
deals concluded by these branches, daring to go as far as to contest the
production costs and suggesting money-saving measures." Serge Mallet, Le Salaire de la technique, in: La Nef,
no. 25, Paris 1959, p. 40. For the integrating trend in the United States
here is an amazing statement by a Union leader of the United Automobile
Workers: "Many times . . . we would meet in a union hall and talk about
the grievances that workers had brought in and what we are going to do about
them. By the time I had arranged a meeting with management the next day,
the problem had been corrected and the union didn't get credit for redressing
the grievance. It's is become a battle of loyalties. . . . All the things
we fought for the corporation is now giving the workers. What
we have to find are other things the worker wants which the employer is
not willing to give him. . . . We’re searching. We’re searching." Labor
Looks At Labor. A Conversation, (Santa Barbara: Center for the
Study of Democratic Institutions, 1963) p. 16 f.
21 Is it still necessary
to denounce the ideology of the "managerial revolution?" Capitalist
production proceeds through the investment of private capital for the private
extraction and appropriation of surplus value, and capital is a social instrument
for the domination of man by man. The essential features of this process
are in no way altered by the spread of stock-holdings, the separation of
ownership from management. etc.
22 See p. 9.
23 "neither by
obedience nor by hardness of labor but by the status of being a mere instrument, and the reduction
of man to the state of a thing” Francois Perroux,
La Coexistence pacifique, (Paris, Presses Universitaires,
1958), vol. III, p. 600.
24 Stewart Meacham,
Labor and the Cold War (American Friends Service Committee, Philadelphia
1959), p, 9.
25 Ibid.
26 See p. 27.
27 Karl Marx,
Grondrisse der Kritik der politischen
Oekonomie (Berlin, Dietz Verlag, 1953), p. 592 f. See also p. 596. My translation.
28 Automation and Major Technological
Change, loc. cit., p. 11 f.
29 C. Wright Mills, White Collar
(New
York:
Oxford
University Press, 1956), p. 319f,
30 In the less advanced capitalist
countries, where strong segments of the militant labor movement are still
alive (France, Italy), their force is pitted against that of accelerated
technological and political rationalization authoritarian form. The exigencies
of the international contest are likely strengthen the latter and to make
for adoption of and alliance with the predominant tendencies in the most
advanced industrial areas.
31 For the following
see my Soviet Marxism, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1958).
32 Rousseau, The Social Contract, Book
I, Chap. VII; Book II, ch. VI.-See p. 6.
33 Marx, "Critique
of the Gotha Programme," in Marx and Engels, Selected Works
(Moscow: Foreign Languages Publ. House, 1958), vol. II, p.23.
34 On the difference between built-in
and manageable resistance see my Soviet Marxism. loc. cit., p. 109
ff.
35 "Economic Problems of
Socialism in the U.S.S.R.” (1952), in: Leo Gruliow ed. Current
Soviet Policies, (New York: F. A. Praeger, 1953), p 5, 11, 14.
36 Ibid., p. 14
f.
37 For the following
see the magniBcent books by Rene Dumont, especially Terres vivantes (Paris:
Plon, l961).
38 "Free"
time, not "leisure" time. The latter thrives in advanced industrial
society, but it is unfree to the extent to which it is administered by business
and politics.
39 See p. 2.
40 For a critical
and realistic appraisal of Galbraith's ideological con- Mept See Earl Latham,
"The Body Politic of the Corporation," in: E. S. Mason,
The Corporation in Modern Society (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1959), p. 223, 235 f.
41 "Ignorance
and unconsciousness are such that nationalism continues to flourish. Neither
twentieth century armaments nor industry allow "fatherlands" to
insure their security and their existence except through organisations which
carry weight on a world wide scale in military and economic matters. But
in the East as well as in the West, collective beliefs don't adapt themselves
to real changes. The great powers shape their empires or repair the
architecture thereof without accepting changes in the economic and political
regime which would give effectiveness and meaning to one or the other
of the coalitions,"
(and:)
"Duped by the nation and duped by the class, the suffering masses are
everywhere involved in the harshness of conflict in which their only enemies
are masters who knowingly use the mystifications of industry and power,
The collusion of modem industry and territorial
power is a vice which is more profoundly real than capitalist and communist
institutions and structures and which no necessary dialectic necessarily
eradicates." Francois Perroux, loc. cit.,
vol. III., p. 631-632; 633.